Jump to content

英文维基 | 中文维基 | 日文维基 | 草榴社区

Causal sets: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Short description.
cleaning up history, wikistyle
 
(17 intermediate revisions by 13 users not shown)
Line 3: Line 3:
The '''causal sets''' program is an approach to [[quantum gravity]]. Its founding principles are that [[spacetime]] is fundamentally discrete (a collection of discrete spacetime points, called the elements of the causal set) and that spacetime events are related by a [[partial order]]. This partial order has the physical meaning of the [[causality relation]]s between spacetime events.
The '''causal sets''' program is an approach to [[quantum gravity]]. Its founding principles are that [[spacetime]] is fundamentally discrete (a collection of discrete spacetime points, called the elements of the causal set) and that spacetime events are related by a [[partial order]]. This partial order has the physical meaning of the [[causality relation]]s between spacetime events.


==History==
The program is based on a theorem<ref name="Malament">{{cite journal|last1=Malament|first1=David B.|title=The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime|journal=Journal of Mathematical Physics|date=July 1977|volume=18|issue=7|pages=1399–1404|doi=10.1063/1.523436|bibcode=1977JMP....18.1399M|url=https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02391730/file/Ontological%20Math%5D%5BPhysics%20mirror%20between%20Noether%20and%20Planck.pdf}}</ref> by [[David Malament]] that states that if there is a [[bijection|bijective]] map between two [[past and future distinguishing]] space times that preserves their [[causal structure]] then the map is a [[Conformal map|conformal isomorphism]]. The conformal factor that is left undetermined is related to the volume of regions in the spacetime. This volume factor can be recovered by specifying a volume element for each space time point. The volume of a space time region could then be found by counting the number of points in that region.
For some decades after the formulation of [[general relativity]], the attitude towards Lorentzian geometry was mostly dedicated to understanding its physical implications and not concerned with theoretical issues.<ref name="Surya">{{Cite journal |last=Surya |first=Sumati |date=2019-09-27 |title=The causal set approach to quantum gravity |url=https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s41114-019-0023-1 |journal=Living Reviews in Relativity |language=en |volume=22 |issue=1 |pages=5 |doi=10.1007/s41114-019-0023-1 |issn=1433-8351}}</ref> However, early attempts to use causality as a starting point have been provided by [[Hermann Weyl]] and [[Hendrik Lorentz]].<ref>{{Citation |last=Bell |first=John L. |title=Hermann Weyl |date=2016 |work=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/weyl/ |access-date=2024-11-18 |edition=Winter 2016 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |last2=Korté |first2=Herbert |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri}}</ref> [[Alfred Robb]] in two books in 1914 and 1936 suggested an axiomatic framework where the causal precedence played a critical role.<ref name=Surya /> The first explicit proposal of quantising the causal structure of spacetime is attributed to Sumati Surya<ref name=Surya /> to E. H. Kronheimer and [[Roger Penrose]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Kronheimer |first=E. H. |last2=Penrose |first2=R. |date=1967 |title=On the structure of causal spaces |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S030500410004144X/type/journal_article |journal=Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society |language=en |volume=63 |issue=2 |pages=481–501 |doi=10.1017/S030500410004144X |issn=0305-0041}}</ref> who invented causal spaces in order to "admit structures which can be very different from a manifold''"''. Causal spaces are defined axiomatically, by considering not only causal precedence, but also chronological precedence.

The program of causal sets is based on a theorem<ref name="Malament">{{cite journal|last1=Malament|first1=David B.|title=The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime|journal=Journal of Mathematical Physics|date=July 1977|volume=18|issue=7|pages=1399–1404|doi=10.1063/1.523436|bibcode=1977JMP....18.1399M|url=https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02391730/file/Ontological%20Math%5D%5BPhysics%20mirror%20between%20Noether%20and%20Planck.pdf }}</ref> by [[David Malament]], extending former results by [[Christopher Zeeman]],<ref>E.C. Zeeman, ''[https://archive.today/20130224064640/http://link.aip.org/link/?JMAPAQ/5/490/1 Causality Implies the Lorentz Group]'', J. Math. Phys. 5: 490-493.</ref> and by [[Stephen Hawking]], A. R. King and P. J. McCarthy.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hawking |first=S. W. |last2=King |first2=A. R. |last3=McCarthy |first3=P. J. |date=1976-02-01 |title=A new topology for curved space–time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures |url=https://pubs.aip.org/aip/jmp/article-abstract/17/2/174/224641/A-new-topology-for-curved-space-time-which?redirectedFrom=fulltext |journal=Journal of Mathematical Physics |language=en |volume=17 |issue=2 |pages=174–181 |doi=10.1063/1.522874 |issn=0022-2488}}</ref><ref name=Surya /> Malament's theorem states that if there is a [[bijection|bijective]] map between two [[past and future distinguishing]] space times that preserves their [[causal structure]] then the map is a [[Conformal map|conformal isomorphism]]. The conformal factor that is left undetermined is related to the volume of regions in the spacetime. This volume factor can be recovered by specifying a volume element for each space time point. The volume of a space time region could then be found by counting the number of points in that region.


Causal sets was initiated by [[Rafael Sorkin]] who continues to be the main proponent of the program. He has coined the slogan "Order + Number = Geometry" to characterize the above argument. The program provides a theory in which space time is fundamentally discrete while retaining local [[Lorentz invariance]].
Causal sets was initiated by [[Rafael Sorkin]] who continues to be the main proponent of the program. He has coined the slogan "Order + Number = Geometry" to characterize the above argument. The program provides a theory in which space time is fundamentally discrete while retaining local [[Lorentz invariance]].
Line 18: Line 21:
The set <math>C</math> represents the set of [[Event (relativity)|spacetime event]]s and the order relation <math>\preceq</math> represents the causal relationship between events (see [[causal structure]] for the analogous idea in a [[pseudo-Riemannian manifold#Lorentzian manifold|Lorentzian manifold]]).
The set <math>C</math> represents the set of [[Event (relativity)|spacetime event]]s and the order relation <math>\preceq</math> represents the causal relationship between events (see [[causal structure]] for the analogous idea in a [[pseudo-Riemannian manifold#Lorentzian manifold|Lorentzian manifold]]).


Although this definition uses the reflexive convention we could have chosen the irreflexive convention in which the order relation is [[irreflexive relation|irreflexive]] and [[asymmetric relation|asymmetric]].
Although this definition uses the reflexive convention we could have chosen the irreflexive convention in which the order relation is [[irreflexive relation|irreflexive]] and [[asymmetric relation|asymmetric]].


The [[causal relation]] of a [[Lorentzian manifold]] (without closed [[causal curve]]s) satisfies the first three conditions. It is the local finiteness condition that introduces spacetime discreteness.
The [[causal relation]] of a [[Lorentzian manifold]] (without closed [[causal curve]]s) satisfies the first three conditions. It is the local finiteness condition that introduces spacetime discreteness.
Line 24: Line 27:
== Comparison to the continuum ==
== Comparison to the continuum ==


Given a causal set we may ask whether it can be [[embedding|embedded]] into a [[Lorentzian manifold]]. An embedding would be a map taking elements of the causal set into points in the manifold such that the order relation of the causal set matches the causal ordering of the manifold. A further criterion is needed however before the embedding is suitable. If, on average, the number of causal set elements mapped into a region of the manifold is proportional to the volume of the region then the embedding is said to be ''faithful''. In this case we can consider the causal set to be 'manifold-like'
Given a causal set we may ask whether it can be [[embedding|embedded]] into a [[Lorentzian manifold]]. An embedding would be a map taking elements of the causal set into points in the manifold such that the order relation of the causal set matches the causal ordering of the manifold. A further criterion is needed however before the embedding is suitable. If, on average, the number of causal set elements mapped into a region of the manifold is proportional to the volume of the region then the embedding is said to be ''faithful''. In this case we can consider the causal set to be 'manifold-like'.


A central conjecture to the causal set program is that the same causal set cannot be faithfully embedded into two spacetimes that are not similar on large scales. This is called the ''[[Hauptvermutung]]'', meaning 'fundamental conjecture'. It is difficult to define this conjecture precisely because it is difficult to decide when two spacetimes are 'similar on large scales'.
A central conjecture of the causal set program, called the ''[[Hauptvermutung]]'' ('fundamental conjecture'), is that the same causal set cannot be faithfully embedded into two spacetimes that are not similar on large scales.


It is difficult to define this conjecture precisely because it is difficult to decide when two spacetimes are 'similar on large scales'.
Modelling spacetime as a causal set would require us to restrict attention to those causal sets that are 'manifold-like'. Given a causal set this is a difficult property to determine.
Modelling spacetime as a causal set would require us to restrict attention to those causal sets that are 'manifold-like'. Given a causal set this is a difficult property to determine.


Line 45: Line 49:
== Geometry ==
== Geometry ==


Some geometrical constructions in manifolds carry over to causal sets. When defining these we must remember to rely only on the causal set itself, not on any background spacetime into which it might be embedded. For an overview of these constructions, see.<ref name=Brightwell>{{cite journal |last1=Brightwell |first1=Graham |last2=Gregory |first2=Ruth |title=Structure of random discrete spacetime |journal=Physical Review Letters |date=21 January 1991 |volume=66 |issue=3 |pages=260–263 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.66.260|pmid=10043761 |bibcode=1991PhRvL..66..260B |hdl=2060/19900019113 |hdl-access=free }}</ref>
Some geometrical constructions in manifolds carry over to causal sets. When defining these we must remember to rely only on the causal set itself, not on any background spacetime into which it might be embedded. For an overview of these constructions, see.<ref name=Brightwell>{{cite journal |last1=Brightwell |first1=Graham |last2=Gregory |first2=Ruth |title=Structure of random discrete spacetime |journal=Physical Review Letters |date=21 January 1991 |volume=66 |issue=3 |pages=260–263 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.66.260|pmid=10043761 |bibcode=1991PhRvL..66..260B |hdl=2060/19900019113 |s2cid=32109929 |hdl-access=free }}</ref>


=== Geodesics ===
=== Geodesics ===
Line 77: Line 81:
== Dynamics ==
== Dynamics ==


An ongoing task is to develop the correct [[Dynamics (physics)|dynamics]] for causal sets. These would provide a set of rules that determine which causal sets correspond to physically realistic [[spacetime]]s. The most popular approach to developing causal set dynamics is based on the ''[[sum-over-histories]]'' version of [[quantum mechanics]]. This approach would perform a "sum-over-causal sets" by ''growing'' a causal set one element at a time. Elements would be added according to quantum mechanical rules and [[Interference (wave propagation)|interference]] would ensure a large manifold-like spacetime would dominate the contributions. The best model for dynamics at the moment is a classical model in which elements are added according to probabilities. This model, due to David Rideout and [[Rafael Sorkin]], is known as ''classical sequential growth'' (CSG) dynamics.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Rideout |first1=D. P. |last2=Sorkin |first2=R. D. |title=Classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets |journal=Physical Review D |year=2000 |volume=61 |issue=2 |pages=024002 |arxiv=gr-qc/9904062 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.61.024002|bibcode=2000PhRvD..61b4002R |s2cid=14652530 }}</ref> The classical sequential growth model is a way to generate causal sets by adding new elements one after another. Rules for how new elements are added are specified and, depending on the parameters in the model, different causal sets result.
An ongoing task is to develop the correct dynamics for causal sets. These would provide a set of rules that determine which causal sets correspond to physically realistic spacetimes. The most popular approach to developing causal set dynamics is based on the [[sum-over-histories]] version of [[quantum mechanics]]. This approach would perform a sum-over-causal sets by growing a causal set one element at a time. Elements would be added according to quantum mechanical rules and interference would ensure a large manifold-like spacetime would dominate the contributions. The best model for dynamics at the moment is a classical model in which elements are added according to probabilities. This model, due to David Rideout and [[Rafael Sorkin]], is known as classical sequential growth (CSG) dynamics.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Rideout |first1=D. P. |last2=Sorkin |first2=R. D. |title=Classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets |journal=Physical Review D |year=2000 |volume=61 |issue=2 |pages=024002 |arxiv=gr-qc/9904062 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.61.024002|bibcode=1999PhRvD..61b4002R |s2cid=14652530 }}</ref> The classical sequential growth model is a way to generate causal sets by adding new elements one after another. Rules for how new elements are added are specified and, depending on the parameters in the model, different causal sets result.


In analogy to the [[path integral formulation]] of quantum mechanics, one approach to developing a quantum dynamics for causal sets has been to apply an [[action principle]] in the sum-over-causal sets approach. Sorkin has proposed a discrete analogue for the [[d'Alembertian]], which can in turn be used to define the [[Ricci curvature scalar]] and thereby the ''Benincasa–Dowker action'' on a causal set.<ref>{{cite arXiv |last=Sorkin |first=D. P. |title=Does Locality Fail at Intermediate Length-Scales |date=20 March 2007 |eprint=gr-qc/0703099}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Benincasa |first1=D. M. T. |last2=Dowker |first2=F. |title=The Scalar Curvature of a Causal Set |journal=Phys. Rev. Lett. |date=May 2010 |volume=104 |issue=18 |pages=181301 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.181301|pmid=20482164 |bibcode=2010PhRvL.104r1301B |arxiv=1001.2725 |s2cid=4560654 }}</ref> Monte-Carlo simulations have provided evidence for a continuum phase in 2D using the Benincasa–Dowker action.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Surya |first=S. |title=Evidence for the continuum in 2D causal set quantum gravity |journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity |date=July 2012 |volume=29 |issue=13 |pages=132001 |doi=10.1088/0264-9381/29/13/132001|bibcode=2012CQGra..29m2001S |arxiv=1110.6244 |s2cid=118376808 }}</ref>
In analogy to the [[path integral formulation]] of quantum mechanics, one approach to developing a quantum dynamics for causal sets has been to apply an [[action principle]] in the sum-over-causal sets approach. Sorkin has proposed a discrete analogue for the [[d'Alembertian]], which can in turn be used to define the [[Ricci curvature scalar]] and thereby the Benincasa–Dowker action on a causal set.<ref>{{cite arXiv |last=Sorkin |first=D. P. |title=Does Locality Fail at Intermediate Length-Scales |date=20 March 2007 |eprint=gr-qc/0703099}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Benincasa |first1=D. M. T. |last2=Dowker |first2=F. |title=The Scalar Curvature of a Causal Set |journal=Phys. Rev. Lett. |date=May 2010 |volume=104 |issue=18 |pages=181301 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.181301|pmid=20482164 |bibcode=2010PhRvL.104r1301B |arxiv=1001.2725 |s2cid=4560654 }}</ref> [[Monte Carlo method|Monte-Carlo simulations]] have provided evidence for a continuum phase in 2D using the Benincasa–Dowker action.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Surya |first=S. |title=Evidence for the continuum in 2D causal set quantum gravity |journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity |date=July 2012 |volume=29 |issue=13 |pages=132001 |doi=10.1088/0264-9381/29/13/132001|bibcode=2012CQGra..29m2001S |arxiv=1110.6244 |s2cid=118376808 }}</ref>


== See also ==
== See also ==
Line 105: Line 109:


;Foundations
;Foundations
*L. Bombelli, J. Lee, D. Meyer, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://prola.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v59/i5/p521_1 Spacetime as a causal set]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 59:521-524 (1987) ; (Introduction, Foundations)
*L. Bombelli, J. Lee, D. Meyer, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://prola.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v59/i5/p521_1 Spacetime as a causal set]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 59:521-524 (1987); (Introduction, Foundations)
*C. Moore, ''[http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v60/p655 Comment on "Space-time as a causal set"]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 60, 655 (1988); (Foundations)
*C. Moore, ''[http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v60/p655 Comment on "Space-time as a causal set"]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 60, 655 (1988); (Foundations)
*L. Bombelli, J. Lee, D. Meyer, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v60/p656 Bombelli et al. Reply]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 60, 656 (1988); (Foundations)
*L. Bombelli, J. Lee, D. Meyer, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v60/p656 Bombelli et al. Reply]'', Phys. Rev. Lett. 60, 656 (1988); (Foundations)
*[[Albert Einstein|A. Einstein]], ''Letter to H.S. Joachim'', August 14, 1954; Item 13-453 cited in J. Stachel,“Einstein and the Quantum: Fifty Years of Struggle”, in From Quarks to Quasars, Philosophical Problems of Modern Physics, edited by R.G. Colodny (U. Pittsburgh Press, 1986), pages 380-381; (Historical)
*[[Albert Einstein|A. Einstein]], ''Letter to H.S. Joachim'', August 14, 1954; Item 13-453 cited in J. Stachel,"Einstein and the Quantum: Fifty Years of Struggle", in From Quarks to Quasars, Philosophical Problems of Modern Physics, edited by R.G. Colodny (U. Pittsburgh Press, 1986), pages 380-381; (Historical)
*[[David Finkelstein|D. Finkelstein]], ''[http://prola.aps.org/abstract/PR/v184/i5/p1261_1 Space-time code]'', Phys. Rev. 184:1261 (1969); (Foundations)
*[[David Finkelstein|D. Finkelstein]], ''[http://prola.aps.org/abstract/PR/v184/i5/p1261_1 Space-time code]'', Phys. Rev. 184:1261 (1969); (Foundations)
*[[David Finkelstein|D. Finkelstein]], ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00669395 "Superconducting" Causal Nets]'', Int. J. Th. Phys 27:473(1988); (Foundations)
*[[David Finkelstein|D. Finkelstein]], ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00669395 "Superconducting" Causal Nets]'', Int. J. Th. Phys 27:473(1988); (Foundations)
*G. Hemion, ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00708682 A quantum theory of space and time]''; Found. Phys. 10 (1980), p.&nbsp;819 (Similar proposal)
*G. Hemion, ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00708682 A quantum theory of space and time]''; Found. Phys. 10 (1980), p.&nbsp;819 (Similar proposal)
*J. Myrheim, ''[http://doc.cern.ch//archive/electronic/kek-scan//197808143.pdf Statistical geometry]'', CERN preprint TH-2538 (1978); (Foundations, Historical)
*J. Myrheim, ''[http://doc.cern.ch//archive/electronic/kek-scan//197808143.pdf Statistical geometry]'', CERN preprint TH-2538 (1978); (Foundations, Historical)
*[[Bernhard Riemann|B. Riemann]], ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20160318034045/http://www.maths.tcd.ie/pub/HistMath/People/Riemann/Geom/ Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen]'', The Collected Works of B. Riemann (Dover NY 1953); ; (Historical)
*[[Bernhard Riemann|B. Riemann]], ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20160318034045/http://www.maths.tcd.ie/pub/HistMath/People/Riemann/Geom/ Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen]'', The Collected Works of B. Riemann (Dover NY 1953); (Historical)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00673986 A Finitary Substitute for Continuous Topology]'', Int. J. Theor. Phys. 30 7: 923-947 (1991); (Foundational)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00673986 A Finitary Substitute for Continuous Topology]'', Int. J. Theor. Phys. 30 7: 923-947 (1991); (Foundational)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Does a Discrete Order underly Spacetime and its Metric?'', Proceedings of the Third Canadian Conference on General Relativity and Relativistic Astrophysics, (Victoria, Canada, May, 1989), edited by A. Coley, F. Cooperstock, B.Tupper, pp.&nbsp;82–86, (World Scientific, 1990); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Does a Discrete Order underly Spacetime and its Metric?'', Proceedings of the Third Canadian Conference on General Relativity and Relativistic Astrophysics, (Victoria, Canada, May, 1989), edited by A. Coley, F. Cooperstock, B.Tupper, pp.&nbsp;82–86, (World Scientific, 1990); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ First Steps with Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', General Relativity and Gravitational Physics, (Proceedings of the Ninth Italian Conference of the same name, held Capri, Italy, September, 1990), 68-90, (World Scientific, Singapore), (1991), R. Cianci, R. de Ritis, M. Francaviglia, G. Marmo, C. Rubano, P. Scudellaro (eds.); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ First Steps with Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', General Relativity and Gravitational Physics, (Proceedings of the Ninth Italian Conference of the same name, held Capri, Italy, September, 1990), 68-90, (World Scientific, Singapore), (1991), R. Cianci, R. de Ritis, M. Francaviglia, G. Marmo, C. Rubano, P. Scudellaro (eds.); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ Spacetime and Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', Relativity and Gravitation: Classical and Quantum, (Proceedings of the SILARG VII Conference, held Cocoyoc, Mexico, December, 1990), pages 150-173, (World Scientific, Singapore, 1991), J.C. D’Olivo, E. Nahmad-Achar, M.Rosenbaum, M.P. Ryan, L.F. Urrutia and F. Zertuche (eds.); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ Spacetime and Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', Relativity and Gravitation: Classical and Quantum, (Proceedings of the SILARG VII Conference, held Cocoyoc, Mexico, December, 1990), pages 150-173, (World Scientific, Singapore, 1991), J.C. D'Olivo, E. Nahmad-Achar, M.Rosenbaum, M.P. Ryan, L.F. Urrutia and F. Zertuche (eds.); (Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Forks in the Road, on the Way to Quantum Gravity'', Talk given at the conference entitled “Directions in General Relativity”, held at College Park, Maryland, May, 1993, Int. J. Th. Phys. 36: 2759–2781 (1997); [[arXiv:gr-qc/9706002]]; (Philosophical, Introduction)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Forks in the Road, on the Way to Quantum Gravity'', Talk given at the conference entitled "Directions in General Relativity", held at College Park, Maryland, May, 1993, Int. J. Th. Phys. 36: 2759–2781 (1997); [[arXiv:gr-qc/9706002]]; (Philosophical, Introduction)
*[[Gerardus 't Hooft|G.'t Hooft]], ''Quantum gravity: a fundamental problem and some radical ideas'', Recent Developments in Gravitation (Proceedings of the 1978 Cargese Summer Institute) edited by M. Levy and S. Deser (Plenum, 1979); (Introduction, Foundations, Historical)
*[[Gerardus 't Hooft|G.'t Hooft]], ''Quantum gravity: a fundamental problem and some radical ideas'', Recent Developments in Gravitation (Proceedings of the 1978 Cargese Summer Institute) edited by M. Levy and S. Deser (Plenum, 1979); (Introduction, Foundations, Historical)
*[[Erik Christopher Zeeman|E.C. Zeeman]], ''[https://archive.today/20130224064640/http://link.aip.org/link/?JMAPAQ/5/490/1 Causality Implies the Lorentz Group]'', J. Math. Phys. 5: 490-493; (Historical, Foundations)
*[[Erik Christopher Zeeman|E.C. Zeeman]], ''[https://archive.today/20130224064640/http://link.aip.org/link/?JMAPAQ/5/490/1 Causality Implies the Lorentz Group]'', J. Math. Phys. 5: 490-493; (Historical, Foundations)
Line 140: Line 144:
*D.P. Rideout; ''[http://loops05.aei.mpg.de/index_files/abstract_rideout.html Spatial Hypersurfaces in Causal Set Cosmology]''; Talk given at Loops 05, 10–14 October 2005, Potsdam, [[Max Planck Institute for Gravitational Physics]] (Spatial hyper-surfaces, Dynamics)
*D.P. Rideout; ''[http://loops05.aei.mpg.de/index_files/abstract_rideout.html Spatial Hypersurfaces in Causal Set Cosmology]''; Talk given at Loops 05, 10–14 October 2005, Potsdam, [[Max Planck Institute for Gravitational Physics]] (Spatial hyper-surfaces, Dynamics)
*J. Scargle, ''[http://scipp.ucsc.edu/seminars/experimental/archive_sq07/scargle_4-24-07.ppt Testing Quantum Gravity Theories with GLAST]''; Talk given at Santa Cruz Institute for Particle Physics, April 24, 2007. (Lorentz invariance, Phenomenology)
*J. Scargle, ''[http://scipp.ucsc.edu/seminars/experimental/archive_sq07/scargle_4-24-07.ppt Testing Quantum Gravity Theories with GLAST]''; Talk given at Santa Cruz Institute for Particle Physics, April 24, 2007. (Lorentz invariance, Phenomenology)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; Two Talks given at the 1997 Santa Fe workshop: ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20090114214257/http://t8web.lanl.gov/people/emil/Slides/sf97talks.html A Review of the Causal Set Approach to Quantum Gravity]'' and ''''; Presented at ”New Directions in Simplicial Quantum Gravity” July 28 - August 8, 1997; ;;
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; Two Talks given at the 1997 Santa Fe workshop: ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20090114214257/http://t8web.lanl.gov/people/emil/Slides/sf97talks.html A Review of the Causal Set Approach to Quantum Gravity]'' and ''[https://web.archive.org/web/20090114214257/http://t8web.lanl.gov/people/emil/Slides/sf97talks.html A Growth Dynamics for Causal Sets]''; Presented at "New Directions in Simplicial Quantum Gravity" July 28 - August 8, 1997
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[http://pirsa.org/07010001 Does quantum gravity give rise to an observable nonlocality?]''; Talk given at [[Perimeter Institute]] 17/01/2007 (d'Alembertian, Locality)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[http://pirsa.org/07010001 Does quantum gravity give rise to an observable nonlocality?]''; Talk given at [[Perimeter Institute]] 17/01/2007 (d'Alembertian, Locality)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://loops05.aei.mpg.de/index_files/abstract_sorkin.html Some Insights for Quantum Gravity Derived from Work on Causal Sets]''; Talk given at Loops 05, 10–14 October 2005, Potsdam, [[Max Planck Institute for Gravitational Physics]] (Overview)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://loops05.aei.mpg.de/index_files/abstract_sorkin.html Some Insights for Quantum Gravity Derived from Work on Causal Sets]''; Talk given at Loops 05, 10–14 October 2005, Potsdam, [[Max Planck Institute for Gravitational Physics]] (Overview)
Line 154: Line 158:
*A.R. Daughton, ''[http://www.iop.org/EJ/abstract/0264-9381/15/11/009 An investigation of the symmetric case of when causal sets can embed into manifolds]'', Class. Quantum Grav.15(11):3427-3434 (Nov., 1998) (Manifoldness)
*A.R. Daughton, ''[http://www.iop.org/EJ/abstract/0264-9381/15/11/009 An investigation of the symmetric case of when causal sets can embed into manifolds]'', Class. Quantum Grav.15(11):3427-3434 (Nov., 1998) (Manifoldness)
*J. Henson, ''Constructing an interval of Minkowski space from a causal set'', Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) L29-L35; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0601069]]; (Continuum limit, Sprinkling)
*J. Henson, ''Constructing an interval of Minkowski space from a causal set'', Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) L29-L35; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0601069]]; (Continuum limit, Sprinkling)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, ''On Recovering Continuum Topology from a Causal Set'', J.Math.Phys.48:032501,2007; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0604124]] (Continuum Topology)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, ''On Recovering Continuum Topology from a Causal Set'', J.Math.Phys.48:032501, 2007; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0604124]] (Continuum Topology)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya; ''Spatial Hypersurfaces in Causal Set Cosmology''; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 4743-4752; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0506133v2]]; (Observables, Continuum topology)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya; ''Spatial Hypersurfaces in Causal Set Cosmology''; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 4743-4752; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0506133v2]]; (Observables, Continuum topology)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, ''Stable Homology as an Indicator of Manifoldlikeness in Causal Set Theory'', [[arXiv:0902.0434]] (Continuum topology and homology)
*S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, ''Stable Homology as an Indicator of Manifoldlikeness in Causal Set Theory'', [[arXiv:0902.0434]] (Continuum topology and homology)
Line 173: Line 177:
*R. Ilie, G.B. Thompson, D.D. Reid; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/23/10/002 A numerical study of the correspondence between paths in a causal set and geodesics in the continuum]''; 2006 Class. Quantum Grav. 23 3275-3285 [[arXiv:gr-qc/0512073]](Geodesic length)
*R. Ilie, G.B. Thompson, D.D. Reid; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/23/10/002 A numerical study of the correspondence between paths in a causal set and geodesics in the continuum]''; 2006 Class. Quantum Grav. 23 3275-3285 [[arXiv:gr-qc/0512073]](Geodesic length)
*A.V. Levichev; ''Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure''; Soviet Math. Dokl. 35:452-455, (1987); (Geometry, [[Causal Structure]])
*A.V. Levichev; ''Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure''; Soviet Math. Dokl. 35:452-455, (1987); (Geometry, [[Causal Structure]])
*{{cite journal|last1=Malament|first1=David B.|title=The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime|journal=Journal of Mathematical Physics|date=July 1977|volume=18|issue=7|pages=1399–1404|doi=10.1063/1.523436|bibcode=1977JMP....18.1399M|url=https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02391730/file/Ontological%20Math%5D%5BPhysics%20mirror%20between%20Noether%20and%20Planck.pdf}}
*{{cite journal|last1=Malament|first1=David B.|title=The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime|journal=Journal of Mathematical Physics|date=July 1977|volume=18|issue=7|pages=1399–1404|doi=10.1063/1.523436|bibcode=1977JMP....18.1399M|url=https://aip.scitation.org/doi/10.1063/1.523436 }}
*D.P. Rideout, P. Wallden; ''Spacelike distance from discrete causal order''; [[arXiv:0810.1768]] (Spatial distances)
*D.P. Rideout, P. Wallden; ''Spacelike distance from discrete causal order''; [[arXiv:0810.1768]] (Spatial distances)


;Cosmological constant prediction
;Cosmological constant prediction
*M. Ahmed, S. Dodelson, P.B. Greene, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Everpresent lambda''; Phys. Rev. D69, 103523, (2004) [[arXiv:astro-ph/0209274v1]] ; (Cosmological Constant)
*M. Ahmed, S. Dodelson, P.B. Greene, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Everpresent lambda''; Phys. Rev. D69, 103523, (2004) [[arXiv:astro-ph/0209274v1]]; (Cosmological Constant)
*Y. Jack Ng and H. van Dam, ''A small but nonzero cosmological constant''; Int. J. Mod. Phys D. 10 : 49 (2001) [[arXiv:hep-th/9911102v3]]; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*Y. Jack Ng and H. van Dam, ''A small but nonzero cosmological constant''; Int. J. Mod. Phys D. 10 : 49 (2001) [[arXiv:hep-th/9911102v3]]; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*Y. Kuznetsov, ''On cosmological constant in Causal Set theory''; [[arXiv:0706.0041]]
*Y. Kuznetsov, ''On cosmological constant in Causal Set theory''; [[arXiv:0706.0041]]
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''A Modified Sum-Over-Histories for Gravity''; reported in Highlights in gravitation and cosmology: Proceedings of the International Conference on Gravitation and Cosmology, Goa, India, 14–19 December 1987, edited by B. R. Iyer, Ajit Kembhavi, [[Jayant Narlikar|Jayant V. Narlikar]], and [[C. V. Vishveshwara]], see pages 184-186 in the article by D. Brill and L. Smolin: “Workshop on quantum gravity and new directions”, pp 183–191 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1988); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''A Modified Sum-Over-Histories for Gravity''; reported in Highlights in gravitation and cosmology: Proceedings of the International Conference on Gravitation and Cosmology, Goa, India, 14–19 December 1987, edited by B. R. Iyer, Ajit Kembhavi, [[Jayant Narlikar|Jayant V. Narlikar]], and [[C. V. Vishveshwara]], see pages 184-186 in the article by D. Brill and L. Smolin: "Workshop on quantum gravity and new directions", pp 183–191 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1988); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00670514 On the Role of Time in the Sum-over-histories Framework for Gravity]'', paper presented to the conference on The History of Modern Gauge Theories, held Logan, Utah, July 1987; Int. J. Theor. Phys. 33 : 523-534 (1994); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00670514 On the Role of Time in the Sum-over-histories Framework for Gravity]'', paper presented to the conference on The History of Modern Gauge Theories, held Logan, Utah, July 1987; Int. J. Theor. Phys. 33 : 523-534 (1994); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ First Steps with Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', in R. Cianci, R. de Ritis, M. Francaviglia, G. Marmo, C. Rubano, P. Scudellaro (eds.), General Relativity and Gravitational Physics (Proceedings of the Ninth Italian Conference of the same name, held Capri, Italy, September, 1990), pp.&nbsp;68–90 (World Scientific, Singapore, 1991); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''[http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ First Steps with Causal Sets] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130930154307/http://physics.syr.edu/~sorkin/some.papers/ |date=2013-09-30 }}'', in R. Cianci, R. de Ritis, M. Francaviglia, G. Marmo, C. Rubano, P. Scudellaro (eds.), General Relativity and Gravitational Physics (Proceedings of the Ninth Italian Conference of the same name, held Capri, Italy, September, 1990), pp.&nbsp;68–90 (World Scientific, Singapore, 1991); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Forks in the Road, on the Way to Quantum Gravity'', talk given at the conference entitled “Directions in General Relativity”, held at College Park, Maryland, May, 1993; Int. J. Th. Phys. 36 : 2759–2781 (1997) [[arXiv:gr-qc/9706002]] ; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Forks in the Road, on the Way to Quantum Gravity'', talk given at the conference entitled "Directions in General Relativity", held at College Park, Maryland, May, 1993; Int. J. Th. Phys. 36 : 2759–2781 (1997) [[arXiv:gr-qc/9706002]]; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Discrete Gravity''; a series of lectures to the First Workshop on Mathematical Physics and Gravitation, held Oaxtepec, Mexico, Dec. 1995 (unpublished); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Discrete Gravity''; a series of lectures to the First Workshop on Mathematical Physics and Gravitation, held Oaxtepec, Mexico, Dec. 1995 (unpublished); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Big extra dimensions make Lambda too small''; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0503057v1]]; (Cosmological Constant)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], ''Big extra dimensions make Lambda too small''; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0503057v1]]; (Cosmological Constant)
Line 200: Line 204:
;Black hole entropy in causal set theory
;Black hole entropy in causal set theory
*D. Dou, ''Black Hole Entropy as Causal Links''; Fnd. of Phys, 33 2:279-296(18) (2003); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0302009v1]] (Black hole entropy)
*D. Dou, ''Black Hole Entropy as Causal Links''; Fnd. of Phys, 33 2:279-296(18) (2003); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0302009v1]] (Black hole entropy)
*D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, ''Counting entropy in causal set quantum gravity'' ; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0612074v1]]; (Black hole entropy)
*D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, ''Counting entropy in causal set quantum gravity''; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0612074v1]]; (Black hole entropy)
*D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, ''Evidence for an entropy bound from fundamentally discrete gravity''; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 6195-6213; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0606065v2]] (Black hole entropy)
*D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, ''Evidence for an entropy bound from fundamentally discrete gravity''; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 6195-6213; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0606065v2]] (Black hole entropy)


Line 230: Line 234:
*J. Henson, D. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], S. Surya; ''Onset of the Asymptotic Regime for (Uniformly Random) Finite Orders''; Experimental Mathematics 26, 3:253-266 (2017); (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*J. Henson, D. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]], S. Surya; ''Onset of the Asymptotic Regime for (Uniformly Random) Finite Orders''; Experimental Mathematics 26, 3:253-266 (2017); (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*A.L. Krugly; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1013273214769 Causal Set Dynamics and Elementary Particles]''; Int. J. Theo. Phys 41 1:1-37(2004);; (Quantum Dynamics)
*A.L. Krugly; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1013273214769 Causal Set Dynamics and Elementary Particles]''; Int. J. Theo. Phys 41 1:1-37(2004);; (Quantum Dynamics)
*X. Martin, D. O'Connor, D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''On the “renormalization” transformations induced by cycles of expansion and contraction in causal set cosmology''; Phys. Rev. D 63, 084026 (2001); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0009063]] (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*X. Martin, D. O'Connor, D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''On the "renormalization" transformations induced by cycles of expansion and contraction in causal set cosmology''; Phys. Rev. D 63, 084026 (2001); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0009063]] (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*D.A. Meyer; ''Spacetime Ising models''; (UCSD preprint May 1993); (Quantum Dynamics)
*D.A. Meyer; ''Spacetime Ising models''; (UCSD preprint May 1993); (Quantum Dynamics)
*D.A. Meyer; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00759191 Why do clocks tick?]''; General Relativity and Gravitation 25 9:893-900;; (Quantum Dynamics)
*D.A. Meyer; ''[https://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00759191 Why do clocks tick?]''; General Relativity and Gravitation 25 9:893-900;; (Quantum Dynamics)
*I. Raptis; ''Quantum Space-Time as a Quantum Causal Set'', [[arXiv:gr-qc/0201004v8]]
*I. Raptis; ''Quantum Space-Time as a Quantum Causal Set'', [[arXiv:gr-qc/0201004v8]]
*D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''A classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets'', Phys. Rev. D, 6, 024002 (2000);[[arXiv:gr-qc/9904062]] (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''A classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets'', Phys. Rev. D, 6, 024002 (2000);[[arXiv:gr-qc/9904062]] (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Evidence for a continuum limit in causal set dynamics'' Phys. Rev. D 63:104011,2001; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0003117]](Cosmology, Dynamics)
*D.P. Rideout, [[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Evidence for a continuum limit in causal set dynamics'' Phys. Rev. D 63:104011, 2001; [[arXiv:gr-qc/0003117]](Cosmology, Dynamics)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Indications of causal set cosmology''; Int. J. Theor. Ph. 39(7):1731-1736 (2000); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0003043]]; (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Indications of causal set cosmology''; Int. J. Theor. Ph. 39(7):1731-1736 (2000); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0003043]]; (Cosmology, Dynamics)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Relativity theory does not imply that the future already exists: a counterexample''; Relativity and the Dimensionality of the World, Vesselin Petkov (ed.) (Springer 2007, in press); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0703098v1]]; (Dynamics, Philosophy)
*[[Rafael Sorkin|R.D. Sorkin]]; ''Relativity theory does not imply that the future already exists: a counterexample''; Relativity and the Dimensionality of the World, Vesselin Petkov (ed.) (Springer 2007, in press); [[arXiv:gr-qc/0703098v1]]; (Dynamics, Philosophy)
Line 246: Line 250:
* [http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v59/p521 Space-time as a causal set] - one of the first papers by Luca Bombelli, Joohan Lee, David Meyer, and Rafael D. Sorkin
* [http://link.aps.org/abstract/PRL/v59/p521 Space-time as a causal set] - one of the first papers by Luca Bombelli, Joohan Lee, David Meyer, and Rafael D. Sorkin
* [https://web.archive.org/web/20200116123248/http://www.einstein-online.info/en/spotlight/causal_sets/ Geometry from order: causal sets] - non-technical article by Rafael D. Sorkin on [https://www.einstein-online.info/en/spotlights/quantum/ Einstein Online]
* [https://web.archive.org/web/20200116123248/http://www.einstein-online.info/en/spotlight/causal_sets/ Geometry from order: causal sets] - non-technical article by Rafael D. Sorkin on [https://www.einstein-online.info/en/spotlights/quantum/ Einstein Online]
* [https://iopscience.iop.org/journal/0264-9381/page/Focus-Issue-on-the-Causal-Set-Approach-to-Quantum-Gravity Focus Issue: The causal set approach to quantum gravity] [[Classical and Quantum Gravity]] Vol. 35, 2018


{{Theories of gravitation}}
{{Theories of gravitation}}

Latest revision as of 11:23, 18 November 2024

The causal sets program is an approach to quantum gravity. Its founding principles are that spacetime is fundamentally discrete (a collection of discrete spacetime points, called the elements of the causal set) and that spacetime events are related by a partial order. This partial order has the physical meaning of the causality relations between spacetime events.

History

[edit]

For some decades after the formulation of general relativity, the attitude towards Lorentzian geometry was mostly dedicated to understanding its physical implications and not concerned with theoretical issues.[1] However, early attempts to use causality as a starting point have been provided by Hermann Weyl and Hendrik Lorentz.[2] Alfred Robb in two books in 1914 and 1936 suggested an axiomatic framework where the causal precedence played a critical role.[1] The first explicit proposal of quantising the causal structure of spacetime is attributed to Sumati Surya[1] to E. H. Kronheimer and Roger Penrose,[3] who invented causal spaces in order to "admit structures which can be very different from a manifold". Causal spaces are defined axiomatically, by considering not only causal precedence, but also chronological precedence.

The program of causal sets is based on a theorem[4] by David Malament, extending former results by Christopher Zeeman,[5] and by Stephen Hawking, A. R. King and P. J. McCarthy.[6][1] Malament's theorem states that if there is a bijective map between two past and future distinguishing space times that preserves their causal structure then the map is a conformal isomorphism. The conformal factor that is left undetermined is related to the volume of regions in the spacetime. This volume factor can be recovered by specifying a volume element for each space time point. The volume of a space time region could then be found by counting the number of points in that region.

Causal sets was initiated by Rafael Sorkin who continues to be the main proponent of the program. He has coined the slogan "Order + Number = Geometry" to characterize the above argument. The program provides a theory in which space time is fundamentally discrete while retaining local Lorentz invariance.

Definition

[edit]

A causal set (or causet) is a set with a partial order relation that is

  • Reflexive: For all , we have .
  • Antisymmetric: For all , we have and implies .
  • Transitive: For all , we have and implies .
  • Locally finite: For all , we have is a finite set.

We'll write if and .

The set represents the set of spacetime events and the order relation represents the causal relationship between events (see causal structure for the analogous idea in a Lorentzian manifold).

Although this definition uses the reflexive convention we could have chosen the irreflexive convention in which the order relation is irreflexive and asymmetric.

The causal relation of a Lorentzian manifold (without closed causal curves) satisfies the first three conditions. It is the local finiteness condition that introduces spacetime discreteness.

Comparison to the continuum

[edit]

Given a causal set we may ask whether it can be embedded into a Lorentzian manifold. An embedding would be a map taking elements of the causal set into points in the manifold such that the order relation of the causal set matches the causal ordering of the manifold. A further criterion is needed however before the embedding is suitable. If, on average, the number of causal set elements mapped into a region of the manifold is proportional to the volume of the region then the embedding is said to be faithful. In this case we can consider the causal set to be 'manifold-like'.

A central conjecture of the causal set program, called the Hauptvermutung ('fundamental conjecture'), is that the same causal set cannot be faithfully embedded into two spacetimes that are not similar on large scales.

It is difficult to define this conjecture precisely because it is difficult to decide when two spacetimes are 'similar on large scales'. Modelling spacetime as a causal set would require us to restrict attention to those causal sets that are 'manifold-like'. Given a causal set this is a difficult property to determine.

Sprinkling

[edit]
A plot of 1000 sprinkled points in 1+1 dimensions

The difficulty of determining whether a causal set can be embedded into a manifold can be approached from the other direction. We can create a causal set by sprinkling points into a Lorentzian manifold. By sprinkling points in proportion to the volume of the spacetime regions and using the causal order relations in the manifold to induce order relations between the sprinkled points, we can produce a causal set that (by construction) can be faithfully embedded into the manifold.

To maintain Lorentz invariance this sprinkling of points must be done randomly using a Poisson process. Thus the probability of sprinkling points into a region of volume is

where is the density of the sprinkling.

Sprinkling points as a regular lattice would not keep the number of points proportional to the region volume.

Geometry

[edit]

Some geometrical constructions in manifolds carry over to causal sets. When defining these we must remember to rely only on the causal set itself, not on any background spacetime into which it might be embedded. For an overview of these constructions, see.[7]

Geodesics

[edit]
A plot of geodesics between two points in a 180-point causal set made by sprinkling into 1+1 dimensions

A link in a causal set is a pair of elements such that but with no such that .

A chain is a sequence of elements such that for . The length of a chain is . If every in the chain form a link, then the chain is called a path.

We can use this to define the notion of a geodesic between two causal set elements, provided they are order comparable, that is, causally connected (physically, this means they are time-like). A geodesic between two elements is a chain consisting only of links such that

  1. and
  2. The length of the chain, , is maximal over all chains from to .

In general there can be more than one geodesic between two comparable elements.

Myrheim[8] first suggested that the length of such a geodesic should be directly proportional to the proper time along a timelike geodesic joining the two spacetime points. Tests of this conjecture have been made using causal sets generated from sprinklings into flat spacetimes. The proportionality has been shown to hold and is conjectured to hold for sprinklings in curved spacetimes too.

Dimension estimators

[edit]

Much work has been done in estimating the manifold dimension of a causal set. This involves algorithms using the causal set aiming to give the dimension of the manifold into which it can be faithfully embedded. The algorithms developed so far are based on finding the dimension of a Minkowski spacetime into which the causal set can be faithfully embedded.

  • Myrheim–Meyer dimension

This approach relies on estimating the number of -length chains present in a sprinkling into -dimensional Minkowski spacetime. Counting the number of -length chains in the causal set then allows an estimate for to be made.

  • Midpoint-scaling dimension

This approach relies on the relationship between the proper time between two points in Minkowski spacetime and the volume of the spacetime interval between them. By computing the maximal chain length (to estimate the proper time) between two points and and counting the number of elements such that (to estimate the volume of the spacetime interval) the dimension of the spacetime can be calculated.

These estimators should give the correct dimension for causal sets generated by high-density sprinklings into -dimensional Minkowski spacetime. Tests in conformally-flat spacetimes[9] have shown these two methods to be accurate.

Dynamics

[edit]

An ongoing task is to develop the correct dynamics for causal sets. These would provide a set of rules that determine which causal sets correspond to physically realistic spacetimes. The most popular approach to developing causal set dynamics is based on the sum-over-histories version of quantum mechanics. This approach would perform a sum-over-causal sets by growing a causal set one element at a time. Elements would be added according to quantum mechanical rules and interference would ensure a large manifold-like spacetime would dominate the contributions. The best model for dynamics at the moment is a classical model in which elements are added according to probabilities. This model, due to David Rideout and Rafael Sorkin, is known as classical sequential growth (CSG) dynamics.[10] The classical sequential growth model is a way to generate causal sets by adding new elements one after another. Rules for how new elements are added are specified and, depending on the parameters in the model, different causal sets result.

In analogy to the path integral formulation of quantum mechanics, one approach to developing a quantum dynamics for causal sets has been to apply an action principle in the sum-over-causal sets approach. Sorkin has proposed a discrete analogue for the d'Alembertian, which can in turn be used to define the Ricci curvature scalar and thereby the Benincasa–Dowker action on a causal set.[11][12] Monte-Carlo simulations have provided evidence for a continuum phase in 2D using the Benincasa–Dowker action.[13]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d Surya, Sumati (2019-09-27). "The causal set approach to quantum gravity". Living Reviews in Relativity. 22 (1): 5. doi:10.1007/s41114-019-0023-1. ISSN 1433-8351.
  2. ^ Bell, John L.; Korté, Herbert (2016), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Hermann Weyl", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-11-18
  3. ^ Kronheimer, E. H.; Penrose, R. (1967). "On the structure of causal spaces". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 63 (2): 481–501. doi:10.1017/S030500410004144X. ISSN 0305-0041.
  4. ^ Malament, David B. (July 1977). "The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime" (PDF). Journal of Mathematical Physics. 18 (7): 1399–1404. Bibcode:1977JMP....18.1399M. doi:10.1063/1.523436.
  5. ^ E.C. Zeeman, Causality Implies the Lorentz Group, J. Math. Phys. 5: 490-493.
  6. ^ Hawking, S. W.; King, A. R.; McCarthy, P. J. (1976-02-01). "A new topology for curved space–time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures". Journal of Mathematical Physics. 17 (2): 174–181. doi:10.1063/1.522874. ISSN 0022-2488.
  7. ^ Brightwell, Graham; Gregory, Ruth (21 January 1991). "Structure of random discrete spacetime". Physical Review Letters. 66 (3): 260–263. Bibcode:1991PhRvL..66..260B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.66.260. hdl:2060/19900019113. PMID 10043761. S2CID 32109929.
  8. ^ J. Myrheim, CERN preprint TH-2538 (1978)
  9. ^ Reid, David D. (30 January 2003). "Manifold dimension of a causal set: Tests in conformally flat spacetimes". Physical Review D. 67 (2): 024034. arXiv:gr-qc/0207103. Bibcode:2003PhRvD..67b4034R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.67.024034. S2CID 12748458.
  10. ^ Rideout, D. P.; Sorkin, R. D. (2000). "Classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets". Physical Review D. 61 (2): 024002. arXiv:gr-qc/9904062. Bibcode:1999PhRvD..61b4002R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.61.024002. S2CID 14652530.
  11. ^ Sorkin, D. P. (20 March 2007). "Does Locality Fail at Intermediate Length-Scales". arXiv:gr-qc/0703099.
  12. ^ Benincasa, D. M. T.; Dowker, F. (May 2010). "The Scalar Curvature of a Causal Set". Phys. Rev. Lett. 104 (18): 181301. arXiv:1001.2725. Bibcode:2010PhRvL.104r1301B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.181301. PMID 20482164. S2CID 4560654.
  13. ^ Surya, S. (July 2012). "Evidence for the continuum in 2D causal set quantum gravity". Classical and Quantum Gravity. 29 (13): 132001. arXiv:1110.6244. Bibcode:2012CQGra..29m2001S. doi:10.1088/0264-9381/29/13/132001. S2CID 118376808.

Further reading

[edit]
Introduction and reviews
Foundations
PhD theses
Talks
Manifoldness
  • L. Bombelli, D.A. Meyer; The origin of Lorentzian geometry; Phys. Lett. A 141:226-228 (1989); (Manifoldness)
  • L. Bombelli, R.D. Sorkin, When are Two Lorentzian Metrics close?, General Relativity and Gravitation, proceedings of the 12th International Conference on General Relativity and Gravitation, held July 2–8, 1989, in Boulder, Colorado, USA, under the auspices of the International Society on General Relativity and Gravitation, 1989, p. 220; (Closeness of Lorentzian manifolds)
  • L. Bombelli, Causal sets and the closeness of Lorentzian manifolds, Relativity in General: proceedings of the Relativity Meeting "93, held September 7–10, 1993, in Salas, Asturias, Spain. Edited by J. Diaz Alonso, M. Lorente Paramo. ISBN 2-86332-168-4. Published by Editions Frontieres, 91192 Gif-sur-Yvette Cedex, France, 1994, p. 249; (Closeness of Lorentzian manifolds)
  • L. Bombelli, Statistical Lorentzian geometry and the closeness of Lorentzian manifolds, J. Math. Phys.41:6944-6958 (2000); arXiv:gr-qc/0002053 (Closeness of Lorentzian manifolds, Manifoldness)
  • A.R. Daughton, An investigation of the symmetric case of when causal sets can embed into manifolds, Class. Quantum Grav.15(11):3427-3434 (Nov., 1998) (Manifoldness)
  • J. Henson, Constructing an interval of Minkowski space from a causal set, Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) L29-L35; arXiv:gr-qc/0601069; (Continuum limit, Sprinkling)
  • S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, On Recovering Continuum Topology from a Causal Set, J.Math.Phys.48:032501, 2007; arXiv:gr-qc/0604124 (Continuum Topology)
  • S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya; Spatial Hypersurfaces in Causal Set Cosmology; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 4743-4752; arXiv:gr-qc/0506133v2; (Observables, Continuum topology)
  • S. Major, D.P. Rideout, S. Surya, Stable Homology as an Indicator of Manifoldlikeness in Causal Set Theory, arXiv:0902.0434 (Continuum topology and homology)
  • D.A. Meyer, The Dimension of Causal Sets I: Minkowski dimension, Syracuse University preprint (1988); (Dimension theory)
  • D.A. Meyer, The Dimension of Causal Sets II: Hausdorff dimension, Syracuse University preprint (1988); (Dimension theory)
  • D.A. Meyer, Spherical containment and the Minkowski dimension of partial orders, Order 10: 227-237 (1993); (Dimension theory)
  • J. Noldus, A new topology on the space of Lorentzian metrics on a fixed manifold, Class. Quant. Grav 19: 6075-6107 (2002); (Closeness of Lorentzian manifolds)
  • J. Noldus, A Lorentzian Gromov–Hausdorff notion of distance, Class. Quantum Grav. 21, 839-850, (2004); (Closeness of Lorentzian manifolds)
  • D.D. Reid, Manifold dimension of a causal set: Tests in conformally flat spacetimes, Phys. Rev. D67 (2003) 024034; arXiv:gr-qc/0207103v2 (Dimension theory)
  • S. Surya, Causal Set Topology; arXiv:0712.1648
Geometry
Cosmological constant prediction
  • M. Ahmed, S. Dodelson, P.B. Greene, R.D. Sorkin, Everpresent lambda; Phys. Rev. D69, 103523, (2004) arXiv:astro-ph/0209274v1; (Cosmological Constant)
  • Y. Jack Ng and H. van Dam, A small but nonzero cosmological constant; Int. J. Mod. Phys D. 10 : 49 (2001) arXiv:hep-th/9911102v3; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • Y. Kuznetsov, On cosmological constant in Causal Set theory; arXiv:0706.0041
  • R.D. Sorkin, A Modified Sum-Over-Histories for Gravity; reported in Highlights in gravitation and cosmology: Proceedings of the International Conference on Gravitation and Cosmology, Goa, India, 14–19 December 1987, edited by B. R. Iyer, Ajit Kembhavi, Jayant V. Narlikar, and C. V. Vishveshwara, see pages 184-186 in the article by D. Brill and L. Smolin: "Workshop on quantum gravity and new directions", pp 183–191 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1988); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin; On the Role of Time in the Sum-over-histories Framework for Gravity, paper presented to the conference on The History of Modern Gauge Theories, held Logan, Utah, July 1987; Int. J. Theor. Phys. 33 : 523-534 (1994); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin, First Steps with Causal Sets Archived 2013-09-30 at the Wayback Machine, in R. Cianci, R. de Ritis, M. Francaviglia, G. Marmo, C. Rubano, P. Scudellaro (eds.), General Relativity and Gravitational Physics (Proceedings of the Ninth Italian Conference of the same name, held Capri, Italy, September, 1990), pp. 68–90 (World Scientific, Singapore, 1991); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin; Forks in the Road, on the Way to Quantum Gravity, talk given at the conference entitled "Directions in General Relativity", held at College Park, Maryland, May, 1993; Int. J. Th. Phys. 36 : 2759–2781 (1997) arXiv:gr-qc/9706002; (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin, Discrete Gravity; a series of lectures to the First Workshop on Mathematical Physics and Gravitation, held Oaxtepec, Mexico, Dec. 1995 (unpublished); (PreObservation Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin, Big extra dimensions make Lambda too small; arXiv:gr-qc/0503057v1; (Cosmological Constant)
  • R.D. Sorkin, Is the cosmological "constant" a nonlocal quantum residue of discreteness of the causal set type?; Proceedings of the PASCOS-07 Conference, July 2007, Imperial College London; arXiv:0710.1675; (Cosmological Constant)
  • J. Zuntz, The CMB in a Causal Set Universe, arXiv:0711.2904 (CMB)
Lorentz and Poincaré invariance, phenomenology
  • L. Bombelli, J. Henson, R.D. Sorkin; Discreteness without symmetry breaking: a theorem; arXiv:gr-qc/0605006v1; (Lorentz invariance, Sprinkling)
  • F. Dowker, J. Henson, R.D. Sorkin, Quantum gravity phenomenology, Lorentz invariance and discreteness; Mod. Phys. Lett. A19, 1829–1840, (2004) arXiv:gr-qc/0311055v3; (Lorentz invariance, Phenomenology, Swerves)
  • F. Dowker, J. Henson, R.D. Sorkin, Discreteness and the transmission of light from distant sources; arXiv:1009.3058 (Coherence of light, Phenomenology)
  • J. Henson, Macroscopic observables and Lorentz violation in discrete quantum gravity; arXiv:gr-qc/0604040v1; (Lorentz invariance, Phenomenology)
  • N. Kaloper, D. Mattingly, Low energy bounds on Poincaré violation in causal set theory; Phys. Rev. D 74, 106001 (2006) arXiv:astro-ph/0607485 (Poincaré invariance, Phenomenology)
  • D. Mattingly, Causal sets and conservation laws in tests of Lorentz symmetry; Phys. Rev. D 77, 125021 (2008) arXiv:0709.0539 (Lorentz invariance, Phenomenology)
  • L. Philpott, F. Dowker, R.D. Sorkin, Energy-momentum diffusion from spacetime discreteness; arXiv:0810.5591 (Phenomenology, Swerves)
Black hole entropy in causal set theory
  • D. Dou, Black Hole Entropy as Causal Links; Fnd. of Phys, 33 2:279-296(18) (2003); arXiv:gr-qc/0302009v1 (Black hole entropy)
  • D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, Counting entropy in causal set quantum gravity; arXiv:gr-qc/0612074v1; (Black hole entropy)
  • D.P. Rideout, S. Zohren, Evidence for an entropy bound from fundamentally discrete gravity; Class. Quantum Grav. 23 (2006) 6195-6213; arXiv:gr-qc/0606065v2 (Black hole entropy)
Locality and quantum field theory
Causal set dynamics
  • M. Ahmed, D. Rideout, Indications of de Sitter Spacetime from Classical Sequential Growth Dynamics of Causal Sets; arXiv:0909.4771
  • A.Ash, P. McDonald, Moment Problems and the Causal Set Approach to Quantum Gravity; J.Math.Phys. 44 (2003) 1666-1678; arXiv:gr-qc/0209020
  • A.Ash, P. McDonald, Random partial orders, posts, and the causal set approach to discrete quantum gravity; J.Math.Phys. 46 (2005) 062502 (Analysis of number of posts in growth processes)
  • D.M.T. Benincasa, F. Dowker, The Scalar Curvature of a Causal Set; arXiv:1001.2725; (Scalar curvature, actions)
  • G. Brightwell; M. Luczak; Order-invariant Measures on Causal Sets; arXiv:0901.0240; (Measures on causal sets)
  • G. Brightwell; M. Luczak; Order-invariant Measures on Fixed Causal Sets; arXiv:0901.0242; (Measures on causal sets)
  • G. Brightwell, H.F. Dowker, R.S. Garcia, J. Henson, R.D. Sorkin; General covariance and the "problem of time" in a discrete cosmology; In ed. K. Bowden, Correlations:Proceedings of the ANPA 23 conference, August 16–21, 2001, Cambridge, England, pp. 1–17. Alternative Natural Philosophy Association, (2002).;arXiv:gr-qc/0202097; (Cosmology, Dynamics, Observables)
  • G. Brightwell, H.F. Dowker, R.S. Garcia, J. Henson, R.D. Sorkin; "Observables" in causal set cosmology; Phys. Rev. D67, 084031, (2003); arXiv:gr-qc/0210061; (Cosmology, Dynamics, Observables)
  • G. Brightwell, J. Henson, S. Surya; A 2D model of Causal Set Quantum Gravity: The emergence of the continuum; arXiv:0706.0375; (Quantum Dynamics, Toy Model)
  • G.Brightwell, N. Georgiou; Continuum limits for classical sequential growth models University of Bristol preprint. (Dynamics)
  • A. Criscuolo, H. Waelbroeck; Causal Set Dynamics: A Toy Model; Class. Quantum Grav.16:1817-1832 (1999); arXiv:gr-qc/9811088; (Quantum Dynamics, Toy Model)
  • F. Dowker, S. Surya; Observables in extended percolation models of causal set cosmology;Class. Quantum Grav. 23, 1381-1390 (2006); arXiv:gr-qc/0504069v1; (Cosmology, Dynamics, Observables)
  • M. Droste, Universal homogeneous causal sets, J. Math. Phys. 46, 122503 (2005); arXiv:gr-qc/0510118; (Past-finite causal sets)
  • J. Henson, D. Rideout, R.D. Sorkin, S. Surya; Onset of the Asymptotic Regime for (Uniformly Random) Finite Orders; Experimental Mathematics 26, 3:253-266 (2017); (Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • A.L. Krugly; Causal Set Dynamics and Elementary Particles; Int. J. Theo. Phys 41 1:1-37(2004);; (Quantum Dynamics)
  • X. Martin, D. O'Connor, D.P. Rideout, R.D. Sorkin; On the "renormalization" transformations induced by cycles of expansion and contraction in causal set cosmology; Phys. Rev. D 63, 084026 (2001); arXiv:gr-qc/0009063 (Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • D.A. Meyer; Spacetime Ising models; (UCSD preprint May 1993); (Quantum Dynamics)
  • D.A. Meyer; Why do clocks tick?; General Relativity and Gravitation 25 9:893-900;; (Quantum Dynamics)
  • I. Raptis; Quantum Space-Time as a Quantum Causal Set, arXiv:gr-qc/0201004v8
  • D.P. Rideout, R.D. Sorkin; A classical sequential growth dynamics for causal sets, Phys. Rev. D, 6, 024002 (2000);arXiv:gr-qc/9904062 (Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • D.P. Rideout, R.D. Sorkin; Evidence for a continuum limit in causal set dynamics Phys. Rev. D 63:104011, 2001; arXiv:gr-qc/0003117(Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • R.D. Sorkin; Indications of causal set cosmology; Int. J. Theor. Ph. 39(7):1731-1736 (2000); arXiv:gr-qc/0003043; (Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • R.D. Sorkin; Relativity theory does not imply that the future already exists: a counterexample; Relativity and the Dimensionality of the World, Vesselin Petkov (ed.) (Springer 2007, in press); arXiv:gr-qc/0703098v1; (Dynamics, Philosophy)
  • M. Varadarajan, D.P. Rideout; A general solution for classical sequential growth dynamics of Causal Sets; Phys. Rev. D 73 (2006) 104021; arXiv:gr-qc/0504066v3; (Cosmology, Dynamics)
  • M.R., Khoshbin-e-Khoshnazar (2013). "Binding Energy of the Very Early Universe: Abandoning Einstein for a Discretized Three–Torus Poset.A Proposal on the Origin of Dark Energy". Gravitation and Cosmology. 19 (2): 106–113. Bibcode:2013GrCo...19..106K. doi:10.1134/s0202289313020059. S2CID 121288092.;(Dynamics, Poset)
[edit]