Jump to content

英文维基 | 中文维基 | 日文维基 | 草榴社区

George Boole

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

George Boole
Portrait of Boole, from
The Illustrated London News, 21 January 1865
Born(1815-11-02)2 November 1815
Died8 December 1864(1864-12-08) (aged 49)
Ballintemple, Cork, Ireland
EducationBainbridge's Commercial Academy[1]
Known for
Spouse
(m. 1855)
Awards
Scientific career
FieldsMathematics
Institutions

Philosophy career
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolBritish algebraic logic[3]
Main interests
Mathematics, logic, philosophy of mathematics

George Boole Jnr FRS (/bl/; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ireland. He worked in the fields of differential equations and algebraic logic, and is best known as the author of The Laws of Thought (1854), which contains Boolean algebra. Boolean logic, essential to computer programming,[4] is credited with helping to lay the foundations for the Information Age.[5][6][7]

Boole was the son of a shoemaker. He received a primary school education and learned Latin and modern languages through various means. At 16, he began teaching to support his family. He established his own school at 19 and later ran a boarding school in Lincoln. Boole was an active member of local societies and collaborated with fellow mathematicians.

In 1849, Boole was appointed the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork (now University College Cork) in Ireland, where he met his future wife, Mary Everest. He continued his involvement in social causes and maintained connections with Lincoln. In 1864, Boole died due to fever-induced pleural effusion after developing pneumonia.

Boole published around 50 articles and several separate publications in his lifetime. Some of his key works include a paper on early invariant theory and "The Mathematical Analysis of Logic," which introduced symbolic logic. Boole also wrote two systematic treatises: "Treatise on Differential Equations" and "Treatise on the Calculus of Finite Differences." He contributed to the theory of linear differential equations and the study of the sum of residues of a rational function. In 1847, Boole developed Boolean algebra, a fundamental concept in binary logic, which laid the groundwork for the algebra of logic tradition and forms the foundation of digital circuit design and modern computer science. Boole also attempted to discover a general method in probabilities, focusing on determining the consequent probability of events logically connected to given probabilities. His work was expanded upon by various scholars, such as Charles Sanders Peirce and William Stanley Jevons. Boole's ideas later gained practical applications when Claude Shannon and Victor Shestakov employed Boolean algebra to optimize the design of electromechanical relay systems, leading to the development of modern electronic digital computers. University College Cork celebrated the 200th anniversary of Boole's birth in 2015, highlighting his significant impact on the digital age.

Boole's contributions to mathematics earned him various honours, including the Royal Society's first gold prize for mathematics, the Keith Medal, and honorary degrees from the Universities of Dublin and Oxford.

Early life

[edit]
Boole's House and School in Lincoln
House and School at 3 Pottergate
Plaque from the house

Boole was born in 1815 in Lincoln, Lincolnshire, England, the son of John Boole Snr (1779–1848), a shoemaker[8] and Mary Ann Joyce.[9] He had a primary school education, and received lessons from his father, but due to a serious decline in business, he had little further formal and academic teaching.[10] William Brooke, a bookseller in Lincoln, may have helped him with Latin, which he may also have learned at the school of Thomas Bainbridge. He was self-taught in modern languages.[2] In fact, when a local newspaper printed his translation of a Latin poem, a scholar accused him of plagiarism under the pretence that he was not capable of such achievements.[11] At age 16, Boole became the breadwinner for his parents and three younger siblings, taking up a junior teaching position in Doncaster at Heigham's School.[12] He taught briefly in Liverpool.[1]

Greyfriars, Lincoln, which housed the Mechanic's Institute

Boole participated in the Lincoln Mechanics' Institute, in the Greyfriars, Lincoln, which was founded in 1833.[2][13] Edward Bromhead, who knew John Boole through the institution, helped George Boole with mathematics books[14] and he was given the calculus text of Sylvestre François Lacroix by the Rev. George Stevens Dickson of St Swithin's, Lincoln.[15] Without a teacher, it took him many years to master calculus.[1]

At age 19, Boole successfully established his own school in Lincoln: Free School Lane.[16] Four years later he took over Hall's Academy in Waddington, outside Lincoln, following the death of Robert Hall. In 1840, he moved back to Lincoln, where he ran a boarding school.[1] Boole immediately became involved in the Lincoln Topographical Society, serving as a member of the committee, and presenting a paper entitled "On the origin, progress, and tendencies of polytheism, especially amongst the ancient Egyptians and Persians, and in modern India".[17]

Boole became a prominent local figure, an admirer of John Kaye, the bishop.[18] He took part in the local campaign for early closing.[2] With Edmund Larken and others he set up a building society in 1847.[19] He associated also with the Chartist Thomas Cooper, whose wife was a relation.[20]

From 1838 onwards, Boole was making contacts with sympathetic British academic mathematicians and reading more widely. He studied algebra in the form of symbolic methods, as far as these were understood at the time, and began to publish research papers.[1]

Professorship and life in Cork

[edit]
The house at 5 Grenville Place in Cork, in which Boole lived between 1849 and 1855, and where he wrote The Laws of Thought (picture taken during renovation)

Boole's status as a mathematician was recognised by his appointment in 1849 as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork (now University College Cork (UCC)) in Ireland. He met his future wife, Mary Everest, there in 1850 while she was visiting her uncle John Ryall who was professor of Greek. They married in 1855.[21][22] He maintained his ties with Lincoln, working there with E. R. Larken in a campaign to reduce prostitution.[23]

In 1861, Boole was involved in a Judgement in the Court of Queen's Bench in Ireland against one John Hewitt Wheatley of Craig House, Sligo for the sum of £400, whereby Wheatley's estate and interest in lands of Maghan/Mahon, County Cork became vested in Boole.[24]

In March 1863, Boole leased Litchfield Cottage, Cork, the house in which he would live with his wife Mary until his death in December of the following year.[25] The premises was described in the deeds as "all that and those the dwelling house called Litchfield Cottage with the premises and appurtenances thereunto belonging and the Garden and Walled in field to the rere thereof". Boole's will bequeathed all his 'estate term and interest' in the lease of Litchfield Cottage unto his wife.[26] In August 1865, some 8 months after his death, Mary (by then living at 68 Harley Street, London) passed the house on to Francis Heard of Ballintemple, Cork, Esquire, a captain in her Majesty's 87th Regiment of South Cork.

Honours and awards

[edit]
Stained glass window in Lincoln Cathedral dedicated to Boole
Detail depicting his favourite Bible passage (content suggested by his widow), God's calling of the prophet Samuel (1 Samuel 3:1–10), a child dedicated to God by his parents[27]
Plaque beneath window

In 1844, Boole's paper "On a General Method in Analysis" won the first gold prize for mathematics awarded by the Royal Society.[28] He was awarded the Keith Medal by the Royal Society of Edinburgh in 1855[29] and was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society (FRS) in 1857.[15] He received honorary degrees of LL.D. from the University of Dublin and the University of Oxford.[30]

Works

[edit]

Boole's first published paper was "Researches in the theory of analytical transformations, with a special application to the reduction of the general equation of the second order", printed in the Cambridge Mathematical Journal in February 1840 (Volume 2, No. 8, pp. 64–73), and it led to his friendship with Duncan Farquharson Gregory, the editor of the journal.[21] His works are in about 50 articles and a few separate publications.[31][23]

In 1841, Boole published an influential paper in early invariant theory.[15] He received a medal from the Royal Society for his memoir of 1844, "On a General Method in Analysis".[21] It was a contribution to the theory of linear differential equations, moving from the case of constant coefficients on which he had already published, to variable coefficients.[32] The innovation in operational methods is to admit that operations may not commute.[33] In 1847, Boole published The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, the first of his works on symbolic logic.[34]

Differential equations

[edit]

Boole completed two systematic treatises on mathematical subjects during his lifetime. The Treatise on Differential Equations[35] appeared in 1859, and was followed, the next year, by a Treatise on the Calculus of Finite Differences,[36] a sequel to the former work.[21] Shortly after his death, Todhunter republished Boole's treatise with some of Boole's revisions, along with a supplement that was originally intended to be merged in the making of the second edition.

Analysis

[edit]

In 1857, Boole published the treatise "On the Comparison of Transcendent, with Certain Applications to the Theory of Definite Integrals",[37] in which he studied the sum of residues of a rational function. Among other results, he proved what is now called Boole's identity:

for any real numbers ak > 0, bk, and t > 0.[38] Generalisations of this identity play an important role in the theory of the Hilbert transform.[38]

Binary logic

[edit]

In 1847, Boole published the pamphlet Mathematical Analysis of Logic. He later regarded it as a flawed exposition of his logical system and wanted An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities to be seen as the mature statement of his views.[21] Contrary to widespread belief, Boole never intended to criticise or disagree with the main principles of Aristotle's logic. Rather he intended to systematise it, to provide it with a foundation, and to extend its range of applicability.[39] Boole's initial involvement in logic was prompted by a current debate on quantification, between Sir William Hamilton who supported the theory of "quantification of the predicate", and Boole's supporter Augustus De Morgan who advanced a version of De Morgan duality, as it is now called. Boole's approach was ultimately much further reaching than either sides' in the controversy.[40] It founded what was first known as the "algebra of logic" tradition.[41]

Among his many innovations is his principle of wholistic reference, which was later, and probably independently, adopted by Gottlob Frege and by logicians who subscribe to standard first-order logic. A 2003 article[42] provides a systematic comparison and critical evaluation of Aristotelian logic and Boolean logic; it also reveals the centrality of holistic reference in Boole's philosophy of logic.

1854 definition of the universe of discourse

[edit]

In every discourse, whether of the mind conversing with its own thoughts, or of the individual in his intercourse with others, there is an assumed or expressed limit within which the subjects of its operation are confined. The most unfettered discourse is that in which the words we use are understood in the widest possible application, and for them, the limits of discourse are co-extensive with those of the universe itself. But more usually we confine ourselves to a less spacious field. Sometimes, in discoursing of men we imply (without expressing the limitation) that it is of men only under certain circumstances and conditions that we speak, as of civilised men, or of men in the vigour of life, or of men under some other condition or relation. Now, whatever may be the extent of the field within which all the objects of our discourse are found, that field may properly be termed the universe of discourse. Furthermore, this universe of discourse is in the strictest sense the ultimate subject of the discourse.[43]

Treatment of addition in logic

[edit]

Boole conceived of "elective symbols" of his kind as an algebraic structure. But this general concept was not available to him: he did not have the segregation standard in abstract algebra of postulated (axiomatic) properties of operations, and deduced properties.[44] His work was a beginning to the algebra of sets, again not a concept available to Boole as a familiar model. His pioneering efforts encountered specific difficulties, and the treatment of addition was an obvious difficulty in the early days.

Boole replaced the operation of multiplication by the word "and" and addition by the word "or". But in Boole's original system, + was a partial operation: in the language of set theory it would correspond only to disjoint union of subsets. Later authors changed the interpretation, commonly reading it as exclusive or, or in set theory terms symmetric difference; this step means that addition is always defined.[41][45]

In fact, there is the other possibility, that + should be read as disjunction.[44] This other possibility extends from the disjoint union case, where exclusive or and non-exclusive or both give the same answer. Handling this ambiguity was an early problem of the theory, reflecting the modern use of both Boolean rings and Boolean algebras (which are simply different aspects of one type of structure). Boole and Jevons struggled over just this issue in 1863, in the form of the correct evaluation of x + x. Jevons argued for the result x, which is correct for + as disjunction. Boole kept the result as something undefined. He argued against the result 0, which is correct for exclusive or, because he saw the equation x + x = 0 as implying x = 0, a false analogy with ordinary algebra.[15]

Probability theory

[edit]

The second part of the Laws of Thought contained a corresponding attempt to discover a general method in probabilities. Here the goal was algorithmic: from the given probabilities of any system of events, to determine the consequent probability of any other event logically connected with those events.[46][21]

Death

[edit]
Boole's gravestone in Blackrock, Cork, Ireland

In late November 1864, Boole walked, in heavy rain, from his home at Lichfield Cottage in Ballintemple[47] to the university, a distance of three miles, and lectured wearing his wet clothes.[48] He soon became ill, developing pneumonia. As his wife believed that remedies should resemble their cause, she wrapped him in wet blankets – the wet having brought on his illness.[48][49][50] Boole's condition worsened and on 8 December 1864,[51] he died of fever-induced pleural effusion.

He was buried in the Church of Ireland cemetery of St Michael's, Church Road, Blackrock (a suburb of Cork). There is a commemorative plaque inside the adjoining church.[52]

Legacy

[edit]
Bust of Boole at University College Cork

Boole is the namesake of the branch of algebra known as Boolean algebra, as well as the namesake of the lunar crater Boole. The keyword Bool represents a Boolean data type in many programming languages, though Pascal and Java, among others, both use the full name Boolean.[53] The library, underground lecture theatre complex and the Boole Centre for Research in Informatics[54] at University College Cork are named in his honour. A road called Boole Heights in Bracknell, Berkshire is named after him.

19th-century development

[edit]

Boole's work was extended and refined by a number of writers, beginning with William Stanley Jevons, who also authored the article about Boole in the Encyclopaedia Britannica. Augustus De Morgan had worked on the logic of relations, and Charles Sanders Peirce integrated his work with Boole's during the 1870s.[55] Other significant figures were Platon Sergeevich Poretskii, and William Ernest Johnson. The conception of a Boolean algebra structure on equivalent statements of a propositional calculus is credited to Hugh MacColl (1877), in work surveyed 15 years later by Johnson.[55] Surveys of these developments were published by Ernst Schröder, Louis Couturat, and Clarence Irving Lewis.

20th-century development

[edit]
In modern notation, the free Boolean algebra on basic propositions p and q arranged in a Hasse diagram. The Boolean combinations make up 16 different propositions, and the lines show which are logically related.

In 1921, the economist John Maynard Keynes published a book on probability theory, A Treatise of Probability. Keynes believed that Boole had made a fundamental error in his definition of independence which vitiated much of his analysis.[56] In his book The Last Challenge Problem, David Miller provides a general method in accord with Boole's system and attempts to solve the problems recognised earlier by Keynes and others. Theodore Hailperin showed much earlier that Boole had used the correct mathematical definition of independence in his worked out problems.[57]

Boole's work and that of later logicians initially appeared to have no engineering uses. Claude Shannon attended a philosophy class at the University of Michigan which introduced him to Boole's studies. Shannon recognised that Boole's work could form the basis of mechanisms and processes in the real world and that it was therefore highly relevant. In 1937 Shannon went on to write a master's thesis, at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, in which he showed how Boolean algebra could optimise the design of systems of electromechanical relays then used in telephone routing switches. He also proved that circuits with relays could solve Boolean algebra problems. Employing the properties of electrical switches to process logic is the basic concept that underlies all modern electronic digital computers. Victor Shestakov at Moscow State University (1907–1987) proposed a theory of electric switches based on Boolean logic even earlier than Claude Shannon in 1935 on the testimony of Soviet logicians and mathematicians Sofya Yanovskaya, Gaaze-Rapoport, Roland Dobrushin, Lupanov, Medvedev and Uspensky. But the first publication of Shestakov's result took place only in 1941 (in Russian). Hence, Boolean algebra became the foundation of practical digital circuit design; and Boole, via Shannon and Shestakov, provided the theoretical grounding for the Information Age.[58]

21st-century celebration

[edit]

"Boole's legacy surrounds us everywhere, in the computers, information storage and retrieval, electronic circuits and controls that support life, learning and communications in the 21st century. His pivotal advances in mathematics, logic and probability provided the essential groundwork for modern mathematics, microelectronic engineering and computer science."

—University College Cork.[5]

The year 2015 saw the 200th anniversary of Boole's birth. To mark the bicentenary year, University College Cork joined admirers of Boole around the world to celebrate his life and legacy.

UCC's George Boole 200[59] project, featured events, student outreach activities and academic conferences on Boole's legacy in the digital age, including a new edition of Desmond MacHale's 1985 biography The Life and Work of George Boole: A Prelude to the Digital Age,[60] 2014.

The search engine Google marked the 200th anniversary of his birth on 2 November 2015 with an algebraic reimaging of its Google Doodle.[5]

5, Grenville Place in 2017 following restoration by UCC
The artwork depicts Boole at a blackboard teaching a boy and girl that the symbols of logic are subject to a special law.
Bronze statue of Boole located at Lincoln Central Train Station. The design, by sculptor Antony Dufort, was funded in part by the Heslam Trust.

In September 2022, a statue of George Boole in his role as a teacher was unveiled at Lincoln Central Train Station, in Boole's home town of Lincoln.

Views

[edit]

Boole's views were given in four published addresses: The Genius of Sir Isaac Newton; The Right Use of Leisure; The Claims of Science; and The Social Aspect of Intellectual Culture.[21] The first of these was from 1835 when Charles Anderson-Pelham, 1st Earl of Yarborough gave a bust of Newton to the Mechanics' Institute in Lincoln.[61] The second justified and celebrated in 1847 the outcome of the successful campaign for early closing in Lincoln, headed by Alexander Leslie-Melville, of Branston Hall.[62] The Claims of Science was given in 1851 at Queen's College, Cork.[63] The Social Aspect of Intellectual Culture was also given in Cork, in 1855 to the Cuvierian Society.[64]

Though his biographer Des MacHale describes Boole as an "agnostic deist",[65][66] Boole read a wide variety of Christian theology. Combining his interests in mathematics and theology, he compared the Christian trinity of Father, Son, and Holy Ghost with the three dimensions of space, and was attracted to the Hebrew conception of God as an absolute unity. Boole considered converting to Judaism but in the end was said to have chosen Unitarianism.[reference?] Boole came to speak against what he saw as "prideful" scepticism, and instead favoured the belief in a "Supreme Intelligent Cause".[67] He also declared "I firmly believe, for the accomplishment of a purpose of the Divine Mind."[68][69] In addition, he stated "To infer the existence of an intelligent cause from the teeming evidence of surrounding design, to rise to the conception of a moral Governor of the World, from the study of the constitution and the moral provisions of our own nature;--these, though but the feeble steps of an understanding limited in its faculties and its materials of knowledge, are of more avail than the ambitious attempt to arrive at a certainty unattainable on the ground of natural religion. And as these were the most ancient, so are they still the most solid foundations, Revelation being set apart, of the belief that the course of this world is not abandoned to chance and inexorable fate."[70][71]

Two influences on Boole were later claimed by his wife, Mary Everest Boole: a universal mysticism tempered by Jewish thought, and Indian logic.[72] Mary Boole stated that an adolescent mystical experience provided for his life's work:

My husband told me that when he was a lad of seventeen a thought struck him suddenly, which became the foundation of all his future discoveries. It was a flash of psychological insight into the conditions under which a mind most readily accumulates knowledge [...] For a few years he supposed himself to be convinced of the truth of "the Bible" as a whole, and even intended to take orders as a clergyman of the English Church. But by the help of a learned Jew in Lincoln he found out the true nature of the discovery which had dawned on him. This was that man's mind works by means of some mechanism which "functions normally towards Monism."[73]

In Ch. 13 of Laws of Thought Boole used examples of propositions from Baruch Spinoza and Samuel Clarke. The work contains some remarks on the relationship of logic to religion, but they are slight and cryptic.[74] Boole was apparently disconcerted at the book's reception just as a mathematical toolset:

George afterwards learned, to his great joy, that the same conception of the basis of Logic was held by Leibniz, the contemporary of Newton. De Morgan, of course, understood the formula in its true sense; he was Boole's collaborator all along. Herbert Spencer, Jowett, and Robert Leslie Ellis understood, I feel sure; and a few others, but nearly all the logicians and mathematicians ignored [953] the statement that the book was meant to throw light on the nature of the human mind; and treated the formula entirely as a wonderful new method of reducing to logical order masses of evidence about external fact.[73]

Mary Boole claimed that there was profound influence – via her uncle George Everest – of Indian thought in general and Indian logic, in particular, on George Boole, as well as on Augustus De Morgan and Charles Babbage:[75]

Think what must have been the effect of the intense Hinduizing of three such men as Babbage, De Morgan, and George Boole on the mathematical atmosphere of 1830–65. What share had it in generating the Vector Analysis and the mathematics by which investigations in physical science are now conducted?[73]

Boole maintained that:

No general method for the solution of questions in the theory of probabilities can be established which does not explicitly recognise, not only the special numerical bases of the science, but also those universal laws of thought which are the basis of all reasoning, and which, whatever they may be as to their essence, are at least mathematical as to their form.[76]

Family

[edit]

In 1855, Boole married Mary Everest (niece of George Everest), who later wrote several educational works on her husband's principles.

The Booles had five daughters:

See also

[edit]

Concepts

[edit]

Other

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ a b c d e O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "George Boole", MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive, University of St Andrews
  2. ^ a b c d Hill, p. 149; Google Books Archived 17 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  3. ^ Ivor Grattan-Guinness (ed.), Companion Encyclopedia of the History and Philosophy of the Mathematical Sciences, Routledge, 2002, ch. 5.1.
  4. ^ Klein, Michael (21 March 2022). "What Boolean Logic Is & How It's Used In Programming". Codecademy. Retrieved 31 August 2024.
  5. ^ a b c "Who is George Boole: the mathematician behind the Google doodle". Sydney Morning Herald. 2 November 2015. Archived from the original on 4 September 2017. Retrieved 20 February 2020.
  6. ^ Nahin, Paul J. (2012). The Logician and the Engineer: How George Boole and Claude Shannon Created the Information Age. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0691176000. JSTOR j.cttq957s.
  7. ^ Mulcahy, Colm (1 November 2015). "The Bicentennial of George Boole, the Man Who Laid the Foundations of the Digital Age". Scientific American Blog Network. Retrieved 30 September 2023.
  8. ^ "John Boole". Lincoln Boole Foundation. Archived from the original on 8 March 2016. Retrieved 6 November 2015.
  9. ^ "George Boole's Family Tree". Archived from the original on 24 February 2021. Retrieved 12 April 2021.
  10. ^ C., Bruno, Leonard (2003) [1999]. Math and mathematicians : the history of math discoveries around the world. Baker, Lawrence W. Detroit, Mich.: U X L. pp. 49. ISBN 0787638137. OCLC 41497065.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  11. ^ C., Bruno, Leonard (2003) [1999]. Math and mathematicians : the history of math discoveries around the world. Baker, Lawrence W. Detroit, Mich.: U X L. pp. 49–50. ISBN 0787638137. OCLC 41497065.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  12. ^ Rhees, Rush. (1954) "George Boole as Student and Teacher. By Some of His Friends and Pupils", Proceedings of the Royal Irish Academy. Section A: Mathematical and Physical Sciences. Vol. 57. Royal Irish Academy
  13. ^ "Society for the History of Astronomy, Lincolnshire". Archived from the original on 1 March 2017. Retrieved 2 September 2019.
  14. ^ Edwards, A. W. F. "Bromhead, Sir Edward Thomas French". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/37224. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
  15. ^ a b c d Burris, Stanley. "George Boole". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  16. ^ George Boole: Self-Education & Early Career Archived 22 November 2017 at the Wayback Machine University College Cork
  17. ^ A Selection of Papers relative to the County of Lincoln, read before the Lincolnshire Topographical Society, 1841–1842. Printed by W. and B. Brooke, High-Street, Lincoln, 1843.
  18. ^ Hill, p. 172 note 2; Google Books Archived 10 June 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  19. ^ Hill, p. 130 note 1; Google Books Archived 27 April 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  20. ^ Hill, p. 148; Google Books Archived 4 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  21. ^ a b c d e f g  One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainJevons, William Stanley (1911). "Boole, George". In Chisholm, Hugh (ed.). Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 4 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 235–236.
  22. ^ Ronald Calinger, Vita mathematica: historical research and integration with teaching (1996), p. 292; Google Books Archived 27 April 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  23. ^ a b Hill, p. 138 note 4; Google Books Archived 27 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  24. ^ Registry of Deeds, Dublin. Memorial: 1863-007-257 (extract). A Memorial of an Indenture of Re-Conveyance bearing date the seventh day of February one thousand eight hundred and sixty three made between William Hutchinson Massey of Mountmassey in the County of Cork, Esquire, of the first part, George Boole of Blackrock in the County of Cork, Esquire, Professor of Mathematics of the second part, Wilhelmina Smithwick of Dunmanway in said County of Cork, Spinster, of the third part and John Hewitt Wheatley of Craig House in the County of Sligo, Esquire, of the fourth part reciting a certain Indenture of Mortgage bearing date the fifth day of January one thousand eight hundred and sixty one whereby the said John Hewitt Wheatley in consideration of the sum.... And reciting that George Boole by the name and description of George Boole of Blackrock in the County of Corke, Professor of Mathematics did in or as of Trinity Term one thousand eight hundred and sixty one obtain a Judgement in the Court of Queen's Bench in Ireland against said John Hewitt Wheatley for the sum of four hundred pounds debt besides costs And reciting that said Judgement was duly registered on the ninth of November one thousand eight hundred and sixty one whereby pursuant to the statute in such Case made and provided the Estate and interest of the said John Hewitt Wheatley in said lands and premises became vested in one George Boole but subject to Redemption...
  25. ^ Registry of Deeds, Dublin. Memorial: 1863-011-164 (extract). Registered: 30/03/1863. Memorial of an Intended Deed [..] made between Edwards Casey then of Waterloo Place in the City of Cork, Esquire [..] and George Boole then of Blackrock in the County of Cork, Esquire, L.L.D. then Professor of Mathematics in the Queens College at Cork [..] After reciting that by Indenture of Lease bearing date the Twenty seventh day of March one thousand eight hundred and fifty six, John Litchfield then of Ballymaloo in the County of Cork, Esquire, did for the considerations therein mentioned demise and set unto the said William Jackson Cummins All That and Those the dwelling house with the premises and the Garden and walled in field to the rere thereof hereinafter particularly mentioned and described To Hold the said demised premises [..] To Hold the said dwelling house and premises with the appurtenances unto the said George Boole, his Executors, Administrators and Assigns, from thenceforth for the then residue of the said term of one hundred years then to come and unexpired vested in him the said Edwards Casey...
  26. ^ Registry of Deeds, Dublin. Memorial: 1865-030-121 (extract). Registered: 20/10/1865. Memorial of a certain Deed of Assignment bearing date the Twenty first day of August one thousand eight hundred and sixty five and made between Mary Boole of 68 Harley Street, London, Widow and Executrix of the Last Will and Testament of George Boole late of Litchfield Cottage Blackrock in the County of Cork Esquire L.L.D. deceased of the one part and Francis Heard of Ballintemple in the County of Cork, Esquire, Captain in her Majesty’s eighty seventh Regiment of South Cork, Militia of the other part Whereby after reciting that by Indenture of Lease bearing date the twenty seventh day of March one thousand eight hundred and fifty six made between John Litchfield of Ballymaloo in the County of Cork, Esquire, of the one part and William Jackson Cummins of the City of Cork, Doctor in Medicine of the other part, the said John Litchfield demised unto the said William Jackson Cummins All that and those the dwelling house called Litchfield Cottage with the premises and appurtenances thereunto [..] also reciting that the said George Boole [..] having before his death duly made and published his last Will and Testament in writing and thereby bequeathed all his Estate term and interest in said hereinbefore recited Indenture of Lease and premises thereby demised unto the said Mary Boole party of said deed of which this is the Memorial and said Will was afterwards duly proved by the said Mary Boole in the Court of Probate District of Cork... witnesses as to the execution of said Deed and this Memorial by the said Mary Boole are witnessed by John Knights, Porter at Queens College, Harley Street, London and Jane White, Housekeeper 68 Harley Street, London.
  27. ^ "Lincoln Cathedral | Things to do". Archived from the original on 9 November 2019. Retrieved 16 November 2019.
  28. ^ MacHale, Desmond. The Life and Work of George Boole: A Prelude to the Digital Age. p. 97.
  29. ^ "Keith Awards 1827–1890". Earth and Environmental Science Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh. 36 (3). Cambridge Journals Online: 767–770. January 1892. doi:10.1017/S0080456800037984. S2CID 251574207. Archived from the original on 20 August 2016. Retrieved 29 November 2014.
  30. ^ Ivor Grattan-Guinness, Gérard Bornet, George Boole: Selected manuscripts on logic and its philosophy (1997), p. xiv; Google Books Archived 22 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  31. ^ A list of Boole's memoirs and papers is in the Catalogue of Scientific Memoirs published by the Royal Society, and in the supplementary volume on differential equations, edited by Isaac Todhunter. To the Cambridge Mathematical Journal and its successor, the Cambridge and Dublin Mathematical Journal, Boole contributed 22 articles in all. In the third and fourth series of the Philosophical Magazine are found 16 papers. The Royal Society printed six memoirs in the Philosophical Transactions, and a few other memoirs are to be found in the Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh and of the Royal Irish Academy, in the Bulletin de l'Académie de St-Pétersbourg for 1862 (under the name G. Boldt, vol. iv. pp. 198–215), and in Crelle's Journal. Also included is a paper on the mathematical basis of logic, published in The Mechanics' Magazine in 1848.
  32. ^ Andrei Nikolaevich Kolmogorov, Adolf Pavlovich Yushkevich (editors), Mathematics of the 19th Century: function theory according to Chebyshev, ordinary differential equations, calculus of variations, theory of finite differences (1998), pp. 130–2; Google Books Archived 10 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  33. ^ Jeremy Gray, Karen Hunger Parshall, Episodes in the History of Modern Algebra (1800–1950) (2007), p. 66; Google Books Archived 16 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  34. ^ George Boole, The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, Being an Essay towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning Archived 11 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine (London, England: Macmillan, Barclay, & Macmillan, 1847).
  35. ^ George Boole, A treatise on differential equations (1859), Internet Archive.
  36. ^ George Boole, A treatise on the calculus of finite differences (1860), Internet Archive.
  37. ^ Boole, George (1857). "On the Comparison of Transcendent, with Certain Applications to the Theory of Definite Integrals". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. 147: 745–803. doi:10.1098/rstl.1857.0037. JSTOR 108643.
  38. ^ a b Cima, Joseph A.; Matheson, Alec; Ross, William T. (2005). "The Cauchy transform". Quad domains and their applications. Oper. Theory Adv. Appl. Vol. 156. Basel: Birkhäuser. pp. 79–111. MR 2129737.
  39. ^ John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.
  40. ^ Grattan-Guinness, I. "Boole, George". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/2868. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
  41. ^ a b Witold Marciszewski (editor), Dictionary of Logic as Applied in the Study of Language (1981), pp. 194–5.
  42. ^ Corcoran, John (2003). "Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought". History and Philosophy of Logic, 24: 261–288. Reviewed by Risto Vilkko. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 11(2005) 89–91. Also by Marcel Guillaume, Mathematical Reviews 2033867 (2004m:03006).
  43. ^ George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by John Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.
  44. ^ a b Andrei Nikolaevich Kolmogorov, Adolf Pavlovich Yushkevich, Mathematics of the 19th century: mathematical logic, algebra, number theory, probability theory (2001), pp. 15 (note 15)–16; Google Books Archived 17 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  45. ^ Burris, Stanley. "The Algebra of Logic Tradition". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  46. ^ Boole, George (1854). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. London: Walton & Maberly. pp. 265–275. ISBN 9780790592428.
  47. ^ "Dublin City Quick Search: Buildings of Ireland: National Inventory of Architectural Heritage". Archived from the original on 4 November 2016. Retrieved 3 November 2016.
  48. ^ a b Barker, Tommy (13 June 2015). "Have a look inside the home of UCC maths professor George Boole". Irish Examiner. Archived from the original on 3 July 2019. Retrieved 6 November 2015.
  49. ^ C., Bruno, Leonard (2003) [1999]. Math and mathematicians : the history of math discoveries around the world. Baker, Lawrence W. Detroit, Mich.: U X L. pp. 52. ISBN 0787638137. OCLC 41497065.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  50. ^ Burris, Stanley (2 September 2018). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 2 September 2019. Retrieved 2 September 2019 – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  51. ^ "George Boole". Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica, inc. 30 January 2017. Archived from the original on 7 December 2017. Retrieved 7 December 2017.
  52. ^ "Death-His Life-- George Boole 200". Archived from the original on 7 February 2020. Retrieved 10 February 2015.
  53. ^ P. J. Brown, Pascal from Basic, Addison-Wesley, 1982. ISBN 0-201-13789-5, page 72
  54. ^ "Boole Centre for Research in Informatics". Archived from the original on 16 August 2019. Retrieved 18 December 2021.
  55. ^ a b Ivor Grattan-Guinness, Gérard Bornet, George Boole: Selected manuscripts on logic and its philosophy (1997), p. xlvi; Google Books Archived 25 April 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  56. ^ Chapter XVI, p. 167, section 6 of A treatise on probability, volume 4: "The central error in his system of probability arises out of his giving two inconsistent definitions of 'independence' (2) He first wins the reader's acquiescence by giving a perfectly correct definition: "Two events are said to be independent when the probability of either of them is unaffected by our expectation of the occurrence or failure of the other." (3) But a moment later he interprets the term in quite a different sense; for, according to Boole's second definition, we must regard the events as independent unless we are told either that they must concur or that they cannot concur. That is to say, they are independent unless we know for certain that there is, in fact, an invariable connection between them. "The simple events, x, y, z, will be said to be conditioned when they are not free to occur in every possible combination; in other words, when some compound event depending upon them is precluded from occurring. ... Simple unconditioned events are by definition independent." (1) In fact as long as xz is possible, x and z are independent. This is plainly inconsistent with Boole's first definition, with which he makes no attempt to reconcile it. The consequences of his employing the term independence in a double sense are far-reaching. For he uses a method of reduction which is only valid when the arguments to which it is applied are independent in the first sense and assumes that it is valid if they are independent in the second sense. While his theorems are true if all propositions or events involved are independent in the first sense, they are not true, as he supposes them to be, if the events are independent only in the second sense."
  57. ^ "ZETETIC GLEANINGS". Archived from the original on 18 July 2011. Retrieved 10 March 2009.
  58. ^ "That dissertation has since been hailed as one of the most significant master's theses of the 20th century. To all intents and purposes, its use of binary code and Boolean algebra paved the way for the digital circuitry that is crucial to the operation of modern computers and telecommunications equipment."Emerson, Andrew (8 March 2001). "Claude Shannon". The Guardian. United Kingdom. Archived from the original on 10 April 2019. Retrieved 14 December 2016.
  59. ^ "George Boole 200 – George Boole Bicentenary Celebrations". Archived from the original on 21 September 2014.
  60. ^ "Cork University Press". Archived from the original on 8 November 2015. Retrieved 6 November 2014.
  61. ^ James Gasser, A Boole Anthology: recent and classical studies in the logic of George Boole (2000), p. 5; Google Books Archived 10 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  62. ^ Gasser, p. 10; Google Books Archived 11 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  63. ^ Boole, George (1851). The Claims of Science, especially as founded in its relations to human nature; a lecture. Archived from the original on 1 February 2014. Retrieved 4 March 2012.
  64. ^ Boole, George (1855). The Social Aspect of Intellectual Culture: an address delivered in the Cork Athenæum, May 29th, 1855 : at the soirée of the Cuvierian Society. George Purcell & Co. Archived from the original on 1 February 2014. Retrieved 4 March 2012.
  65. ^ International Association for Semiotic Studies; International Council for Philosophy and Humanistic Studies; International Social Science Council (1995). "A tale of two amateurs". Semiotica, Volume 105. Mouton. p. 56. MacHale's biography calls George Boole 'an agnostic deist'. Both Booles' classification of 'religious philosophies' as monistic, dualistic, and trinitarian left little doubt about their preference for 'the unity religion', whether Judaic or Unitarian.
  66. ^ International Association for Semiotic Studies; International Council for Philosophy and Humanistic Studies; International Social Science Council (1996). Semiotica, Volume 105. Mouton. p. 17. MacHale does not repress this or other evidence of the Boole's nineteenth-century beliefs and practices in the paranormal and in religious mysticism. He even concedes that George Boole's many distinguished contributions to logic and mathematics may have been motivated by his distinctive religious beliefs as an "agnostic deist" and by an unusual personal sensitivity to the sufferings of other people.
  67. ^ Boole, George. Studies in Logic and Probability. 2002. Courier Dover Publications. p. 201-202
  68. ^ Boole, George. Studies in Logic and Probability. 2002. Courier Dover Publications. p. 451
  69. ^ Some-Side of a Scientific Mind (2013). pp. 112–3. The University Magazine, 1878. London: Forgotten Books. (Original work published 1878)
  70. ^ Concluding remarks of his treatise of "Clarke and Spinoza", as found in Boole, George (2007). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. Cosimo, Inc. Chap . XIII. p. 217-218. (Original work published 1854)
  71. ^ Boole, George (1851). The claims of science, especially as founded in its relations to human nature; a lecture, Volume 15. p. 24
  72. ^ Jonardon Ganeri (2001), Indian Logic: a reader, Routledge, p. 7, ISBN 0-7007-1306-9; Google Books Archived 19 April 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  73. ^ a b c Boole, Mary Everest Indian Thought and Western Science in the Nineteenth Century, Boole, Mary Everest Collected Works eds. E. M. Cobham and E. S. Dummer, London, Daniel 1931 pp.947–967
  74. ^ Grattan-Guinness and Bornet, p. 16; Google Books Archived 8 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  75. ^ Kak, S. (2018) George Boole’s Laws of Thought and Indian logic. Current Science, vol. 114, 2570–2573
  76. ^ Boole, George (2012) [Originally published by Watts & Co., London, in 1952]. Rhees, Rush (ed.). Studies in Logic and Probability (Reprint ed.). Mineola, New York: Dover Publications. p. 273. ISBN 978-0-486-48826-4. Archived from the original on 5 May 2016. Retrieved 27 October 2015.
  77. ^ "Family and Genealogy – His Life George Boole 200". Georgeboole.com. Archived from the original on 28 August 2017. Retrieved 7 March 2016.
  78. ^ `My Right To Die´, Woman Kills Self in The Washington Times v. 28 May 1908 (PDF Archived 5 June 2012 at the Wayback Machine); Mrs. Mary Hinton A Suicide in The New York Times v. 29 May 1908 (PDF Archived 25 February 2021 at the Wayback Machine).
  79. ^ "|George Boole 200|News".
  80. ^ "Smothers In Orchard" in The Los Angeles Times v. 27 February 1909.
  81. ^ D. MacHale, The Life and Work of George Boole: A Prelude to the Digital Age, Cork University Press, 2014. cited in The Extraordinary Case of the Boole Family Archived 16 November 2019 at the Wayback Machine by Moira Chas

References

[edit]
[edit]