Jump to content

英文维基 | 中文维基 | 日文维基 | 草榴社区

Thomas Bayes

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Thomas Bayes
The only known portrait that is possibly of Bayes from a 1936 book,[1] but it is doubtful whether the portrait is actually of him.[2][3]
Bornc. 1701
London, England
Died7 April 1761(1761-04-07) (aged 59)
Alma materUniversity of Edinburgh
Known forBayesian statistics
Bayes' theorem
Conditional probability
Inverse probability
Bayes prior
Bayes factor
Bayesian inference
See full list
Scientific career
FieldsProbability
Signature

Thomas Bayes (/bz/ BAYZ audio; c. 1701 – 7 April 1761[2][4][note 1]) was an English statistician, philosopher and Presbyterian minister who is known for formulating a specific case of the theorem that bears his name: Bayes' theorem. Bayes never published what would become his most famous accomplishment; his notes were edited and published posthumously by Richard Price.[5]

Biography

[edit]
Mount Sion Chapel, where Bayes served as minister.

Thomas Bayes was the son of London Presbyterian minister Joshua Bayes,[6] and was possibly born in Hertfordshire.[7] He came from a prominent nonconformist family from Sheffield. In 1719, he enrolled at the University of Edinburgh to study logic and theology. On his return around 1722, he assisted his father at the latter's chapel in London before moving to Tunbridge Wells, Kent, around 1734. There he was minister of the Mount Sion Chapel, until 1752.[8]

He is known to have published two works in his lifetime, one theological and one mathematical:

  1. Divine Benevolence, or an Attempt to Prove That the Principal End of the Divine Providence and Government is the Happiness of His Creatures (1731)
  2. An Introduction to the Doctrine of Fluxions, and a Defence of the Mathematicians Against the Objections of the Author of The Analyst (published anonymously in 1736), in which he defended the logical foundation of Isaac Newton's calculus ("fluxions") against the criticism by George Berkeley, a bishop and noted philosopher, the author of The Analyst

Bayes was elected as a Fellow of the Royal Society in 1742. His nomination letter was signed by Philip Stanhope, Martin Folkes, James Burrow, Cromwell Mortimer, and John Eames. It is speculated that he was accepted by the society on the strength of the Introduction to the Doctrine of Fluxions, as he is not known to have published any other mathematical work during his lifetime.[9]

In his later years he took a deep interest in probability. Historian Stephen Stigler thinks that Bayes became interested in the subject while reviewing a work written in 1755 by Thomas Simpson,[10] but George Alfred Barnard thinks he learned mathematics and probability from a book by Abraham de Moivre.[11] Others speculate he was motivated to rebut David Hume's argument against believing in miracles on the evidence of testimony in An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding.[12] His work and findings on probability theory were passed in manuscript form to his friend Richard Price after his death.

Monument to members of the Bayes and Cotton families, including Thomas Bayes and his father Joshua, in Bunhill Fields burial ground

By 1755, he was ill, and by 1761, he had died in Tunbridge Wells. He was buried in Bunhill Fields burial ground in Moorgate, London, where many nonconformists lie.

In 2018, the University of Edinburgh opened a £45 million research centre connected to its informatics department named after its alumnus, Bayes.[13]

In April 2021, it was announced that Cass Business School, whose City of London campus is on Bunhill Row, was to be renamed after Bayes.[13]

Bayes' theorem

[edit]

Bayes's solution to a problem of inverse probability was presented in An Essay Towards Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances, which was read to the Royal Society in 1763 after Bayes's death. Richard Price shepherded the work through this presentation and its publication in the Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London the following year.[14] This was an argument for using a uniform prior distribution for a binomial parameter and not merely a general postulate.[15] This essay gives the following theorem (stated here in present-day terminology).

Suppose a quantity R is uniformly distributed between 0 and 1. Suppose each of X1, ..., Xn is equal to either 1 or 0 and the conditional probability that any of them is equal to 1, given the value of R, is R. Suppose they are conditionally independent given the value of R. Then the conditional probability distribution of R, given the values of X1, ..., Xn, is

Thus, for example,

This is a special case of the Bayes' theorem.

In the first decades of the eighteenth century, many problems concerning the probability of certain events, given specified conditions, were solved. For example: given a specified number of white and black balls in an urn, what is the probability of drawing a black ball? Or the converse: given that one or more balls has been drawn, what can be said about the number of white and black balls in the urn? These are sometimes called "inverse probability" problems.

Bayes's Essay contains his solution to a similar problem posed by Abraham de Moivre, author of The Doctrine of Chances (1718).

In addition, a paper by Bayes on asymptotic series was published posthumously.

Bayesianism

[edit]

Bayesian probability is the name given to several related interpretations of probability as an amount of epistemic confidence – the strength of beliefs, hypotheses etc. – rather than a frequency. This allows the application of probability to all sorts of propositions rather than just ones that come with a reference class. "Bayesian" has been used in this sense since about 1950. Since its rebirth in the 1950s, advancements in computing technology have allowed scientists from many disciplines to pair traditional Bayesian statistics with random walk techniques. The use of the Bayes theorem has been extended in science and in other fields.[16]

Bayes himself might not have embraced the broad interpretation now called Bayesian, which was in fact pioneered and popularised by Pierre-Simon Laplace;[17] it is difficult to assess Bayes's philosophical views on probability, since his essay does not go into questions of interpretation. There, Bayes defines probability of an event as "the ratio between the value at which an expectation depending on the happening of the event ought to be computed, and the value of the thing expected upon its happening" (Definition 5). In modern utility theory, the same definition would result by rearranging the definition of expected utility (the probability of an event times the payoff received in case of that event – including the special cases of buying risk for small amounts or buying security for big amounts) to solve for the probability. As Stigler points out,[10] this is a subjective definition, and does not require repeated events; however, it does require that the event in question be observable, for otherwise it could never be said to have "happened". Stigler argues that Bayes intended his results in a more limited way than modern Bayesians. Given Bayes's definition of probability, his result concerning the parameter of a binomial distribution makes sense only to the extent that one can bet on its observable consequences.

The philosophy of Bayesian statistics is at the core of almost every modern estimation approach that includes conditioned probabilities, such as sequential estimation, probabilistic machine learning techniques, risk assessment, simultaneous localization and mapping, regularization or information theory. The rigorous axiomatic framework for probability theory as a whole, however, was developed 200 years later during the early and middle 20th century, starting with insightful results in ergodic theory by Plancherel in 1913.[citation needed]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Bayes's tombstone says he died at 59 years of age on 7 April 1761, so he was born in either 1701 or 1702. Some sources erroneously write the death date as 17 April, but these sources all seem to stem from a clerical error duplicated; no evidence argues in favour of a 17 April death date. Bayes's birth date is unknown, likely due to the fact he was baptised in a Dissenting church, which either did not keep or was unable to preserve its baptismal records; accord Royal Society Library and Archive catalogue, Thomas Bayes (1701–1761)[2]

References

[edit]

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^ Terence O'Donnell, History of Life Insurance in Its Formative Years (Chicago: American Conservation Co:, 1936), p. 335 (caption "Rev. T. Bayes: Improver of the Columnar Method developed by Barrett.")
  2. ^ a b c Bayes's portrait The IMS Bulletin, Vol. 17 (1988), No. 3, pp. 276–278.
  3. ^ Bellhouse, D. R. (1 February 2004). "The Reverend Thomas Bayes, FRS: A Biography to Celebrate the Tercentenary of His Birth". Statistical Science. 19 (1): 3. Bibcode:2004StaSc..19....3B. doi:10.1214/088342304000000189. ISSN 0883-4237.
  4. ^ Belhouse, D.R. The Reverend Thomas Bayes FRS: a Biography to Celebrate the Tercentenary of his Birth Archived 5 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
  5. ^ McGrayne, Sharon Bertsch. (2011). The Theory That Would Not Die p. 10., p. 10, at Google Books
  6. ^ "Bayes, Joshua" . Dictionary of National Biography. London: Smith, Elder & Co. 1885–1900.
  7. ^ Oxford Dictionary of National Biography, article on Bayes by A. W. F. Edwards.
  8. ^ "The Reverend Thomas Bayes FRS – A Biography" (PDF). Institute of Mathematical Statistics. Retrieved 18 July 2010.
  9. ^ "Lists of Royal Society Fellows 1660–2007" (PDF). London: The Royal Society. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
  10. ^ a b Stigler, S. M. (1986). The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-40340-1.
  11. ^ Barnard, G. A. (1958). "Thomas Bayes—a biographical note". Biometrika. 45: 293–295. doi:10.2307/2333180. JSTOR 2333180.
  12. ^ Cepelewicz, Jordana (20 December 2016). "How a Defense of Christianity Revolutionized Brain Science". Nautilus (science magazine). Retrieved 20 December 2016.
  13. ^ a b "Cass Business School to be renamed after statistician Thomas Bayes". Financial Times. 21 April 2021. Archived from the original on 10 December 2022.
  14. ^ Bayes, Thomas (1763). "An Essay Towards Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances". Philosophical Transactions. 53: 370–418. doi:10.1098/rstl.1763.0053. S2CID 186213794.
  15. ^ Edwards, A. W. G. "Commentary on the Arguments of Thomas Bayes," Scandinavian Journal of Statistics, Vol. 5, No. 2 (1978), pp. 116–118; retrieved 6 August 2011
  16. ^ Paulos, John Allen. "The Mathematics of Changing Your Mind," New York Times (US). 5 August 2011; retrieved 6 August 2011
  17. ^ Stigler, Stephen M. (1986) The history of statistics., Harvard University press. pp 97–98, 131.

Sources

[edit]
[edit]